10.07.2015 Views

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– HERMENEUTIC UNDERSTANDING ––––– 197understand<strong>in</strong>g of what Renan (cited <strong>in</strong> Bettelheim, 1983) called la science de l’humanité maybe illustrated at three levels. Psychoanalysis provides a theoretical basis for understand<strong>in</strong>g boththe objective and subjective aspects of the subject of <strong>research</strong>. Habermas, for example, suggeststhat Freud ‘dealt with the occurrence of systematically deformed communication <strong>in</strong> order <strong>to</strong>def<strong>in</strong>e the scope of specifically <strong>in</strong>comprehensible acts and utterances’ (1970: 349). At a secondlevel, psychoanalytic theory provides an account of the relationship between the <strong>research</strong>erand the subject of <strong>research</strong>. The theory of transference and countertransference (see, forexample McAuley, 1989) shows how <strong>in</strong> the relationship the <strong>research</strong>er and the subject of<strong>research</strong> create a relationship that can be explored reflexively by both parties <strong>in</strong> the situation.At a third level psychoanalysis provides an account of the sett<strong>in</strong>g (Malcolm, 1988) <strong>in</strong> whichthe hermeneutic <strong>research</strong> act can be conducted. Habermas characterizes the analytic sett<strong>in</strong>gas a ‘special design of communication. The fundamental analytic rule . . . ensures a standardrelationship . . . which meets quasi-experimental conditions’ (1970: 352).Some of the ways <strong>in</strong> which the hermeneutic tradition is manifested <strong>in</strong> the psychoanalyticencounter may be seen <strong>in</strong> these ‘rules of conduct’ (cited <strong>in</strong> Malcolm, 1988: 142). These weredistilled by the psychoanalyst W<strong>in</strong>nicott (1958) from Freud’s th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. The key po<strong>in</strong>ts, forpresent purposes, from W<strong>in</strong>nicott’s ideas are <strong>in</strong> italics. They have been <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> relation<strong>to</strong> undertak<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>research</strong> act not only for psychoanalytic framework but <strong>in</strong> the hermeneuticframe generally:• The analyst aims <strong>to</strong> get <strong>in</strong> <strong>to</strong>uch with the process of the client, <strong>to</strong> understand the material and <strong>to</strong>communicate the understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> words. There is a key issue here of <strong>in</strong>terpretation and theadequacy of the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>to</strong> capture and develop the ability <strong>to</strong> understand thesituation. There is, however, additionally <strong>in</strong> this understand<strong>in</strong>g and communication anemancipa<strong>to</strong>ry process whereby it <strong>in</strong>vestigates the communication between therapist andclient (or <strong>in</strong> our case <strong>research</strong>er and the subject of <strong>research</strong>) as ‘an expression of anunconscious symbol-system’ (Giddens, 1982: 86).• The analyst’s method was one of objective observation: on the one hand writers <strong>in</strong> thepsychoanalytic tradition such as Bion (1970) write of the need, <strong>in</strong> the analytic encounter,<strong>to</strong> be able <strong>to</strong> suspend memory (for example of previous encounters), desire (for examplethat the subject ‘likes’ the <strong>research</strong>er), understand<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> the sense of com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>to</strong> animmediate conclusion) and <strong>in</strong>tuitions that are based on a lay rather than professionalunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of the situation. The development of this objectivity comes, so it isclaimed, after years of tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and self-<strong>in</strong>sight.On the other hand there are those who would claim that, given the nature of thehermeneutic cycle the <strong>research</strong>er (whether <strong>in</strong> human or natural science (G<strong>in</strong>ev, 1999))cannot escape from ‘socialized pre-understand<strong>in</strong>gs . . . there is no observation free fromthe observer’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation based on the presuppositions that derive from their <strong>in</strong>itiation<strong>in</strong><strong>to</strong> the ‘know how’ of a particular socio-his<strong>to</strong>rical culture’ (Johnson and Duberley,2000: 66). Contrary <strong>to</strong> this view, Habermas suggests that the analyst’s (<strong>research</strong>er’s)preunderstand<strong>in</strong>g ‘is directed at a small sampl<strong>in</strong>g of possible mean<strong>in</strong>gs’ (1970: 352) – <strong>in</strong>other words is highly focused and therefore amenable <strong>to</strong> tight control.• The analyst keeps out moral judgement, though he/she should not appear unaware of some universalshock. What this refers <strong>to</strong> is that the <strong>research</strong>er is not there <strong>to</strong> make moral judgementsabout the subjects’ values or behaviours. In the case of a morally repugnant encounterthe hermeneutic task is <strong>to</strong> understand what is caus<strong>in</strong>g the repugnance <strong>in</strong> the <strong>research</strong>er’sown <strong>in</strong>ner life.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!