04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

102 HERACLITUS<br />

Honour is <strong>the</strong> best thing <strong>to</strong> choose precisely because it escapes from <strong>the</strong> contextdependence<br />

of o<strong>the</strong>r values, which are desirable only by contrast with some<br />

painful alternative and are confined <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> temporal life of an individual with<br />

desires. Ordinary people, as Clement observes in interpreting this saying,<br />

measure <strong>the</strong>ir happiness by food and sex, <strong>the</strong> values of non-human animals. But<br />

virtue achieves a different kind of reward, one that extends beyond human<br />

recognition: ‘Gods and humans honour <strong>the</strong> war-dead’ (B24). 107<br />

Thus although Heraclitus certainly does not regard <strong>the</strong> values of <strong>the</strong> multitude<br />

as worthy of pursuit, he will not easily find anyone who is qualified <strong>to</strong> rule.<br />

Aris<strong>to</strong>cracy, in place of democracy, will be <strong>the</strong> rule of <strong>the</strong> ‘best’, but <strong>the</strong> best are<br />

defined by <strong>the</strong>ir choice of honour or virtue as <strong>the</strong> only lasting value worthy of<br />

pursuit. ‘It is cus<strong>to</strong>mary <strong>to</strong> respect <strong>the</strong> advice of one’ (B33); 108 ‘One is ten<br />

thousand if he is <strong>the</strong> best’ (B49). 109<br />

Honour transcends context and <strong>the</strong> limitations of a single human life. What is<br />

morally right, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, seems at first <strong>to</strong> be defined by contrast with<br />

wrongdoing; Heraclitus observes that we use <strong>the</strong> term of approval (‘right’) in a<br />

context where we imply a contrast with some alternative:<br />

They would not have known <strong>the</strong> term ‘right’, if <strong>the</strong>re were no such things<br />

as <strong>the</strong>se.<br />

(B23) 110<br />

‘These’ are, we presume (following <strong>the</strong> suggestions offered by Clement when he<br />

quotes <strong>the</strong> text), examples of wrongdoing or misdeeds. But Heraclitus is not<br />

content <strong>to</strong> leave morality in <strong>the</strong> same position as <strong>the</strong> utilitarian values of health,<br />

food and rest. Mortals may in practice define <strong>the</strong>ir notion of what is morally<br />

right by contrasting right with wrong, but in some sense this is an error. We can<br />

notice <strong>the</strong> reference <strong>to</strong> ‘<strong>the</strong>y’ again, which generally accompanies a disparaging<br />

remark on <strong>the</strong> confusion of ordinary mortals. Perhaps, <strong>the</strong>n, what is morally right<br />

does have absolute value that is not dependent upon a respite from an alternative<br />

range of evils, but mortals only learn <strong>to</strong> see it as <strong>the</strong> notion abstracted from <strong>the</strong><br />

absence of certain identifiable wrongs. Yet <strong>the</strong>re would, presumably, be a<br />

meaning for <strong>the</strong> word ‘right’ even were <strong>the</strong>re no wrongs in <strong>the</strong> world at all. That<br />

seems <strong>to</strong> be so for god, because <strong>the</strong>re are no such things as wrong for him.<br />

‘Everything for god is noble and good and right, but humans have taken some <strong>to</strong><br />

be wrong and some right’ (B102). 111 Indeed this fragment suggests that our<br />

perception of evils as evils is observer-related: <strong>the</strong>y are evils for us; and we<br />

confine <strong>the</strong> word ‘good’ <strong>to</strong> what is good for us. But that is <strong>to</strong> make goodness a<br />

merely human value. That mortal usage of right and wrong is out of line with <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute value perceived from <strong>the</strong> god’s eye view. So whereas it may seem <strong>to</strong> us<br />

that we could not appreciate <strong>the</strong> value of goodness in itself without <strong>the</strong> presence<br />

of evil, that is not how things appear <strong>to</strong> one who correctly perceives what <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute value of morality is. Like honour, <strong>the</strong>n, what is absolutely right escapes

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!