04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

350 PLATO: METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY<br />

examples, philosophically important Forms were investigated, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> sort of<br />

argumentation found in <strong>the</strong> Sophist passage might be required. 59<br />

The Theaetetus and <strong>the</strong> Sophist<br />

The Theaetetus represents Pla<strong>to</strong>’s most sustained investigation in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of<br />

knowledge. Structured around an attempt <strong>to</strong> define knowledge, it, like <strong>the</strong> early<br />

dialogues, ends in frustration. But scholars have been quick <strong>to</strong> find positive<br />

lessons which we are meant <strong>to</strong> draw from <strong>the</strong> discussion. 60<br />

The dialogue divides in<strong>to</strong> three sections which consider proposals <strong>to</strong> define<br />

knowledge as (1) perception, (2) true judgement, and (3) true judgement with an<br />

account. (3) resembles contemporary definitions of knowledge in terms of<br />

justified true belief, but one difference is that all three suggestions define<br />

knowledge not as a disposition but as a mental event: perception or judgement,<br />

where judgement occurs when <strong>the</strong> soul says something <strong>to</strong> itself (180e–190a,<br />

Sophist 265e–264a).<br />

(1) Because knowledge is infallible and of what is, if knowledge is perception<br />

<strong>the</strong>n perception is infallible and of what is. Since x may (e.g.) appear warm <strong>to</strong> A<br />

and cold <strong>to</strong> B, (1) entails a Protagorean relativism validating both perceptions:<br />

what A perceives is for A and what B perceives is for B. The object is not warm<br />

or cold in itself: no objective reality independent of <strong>the</strong> perceptions exists that<br />

could falsify <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Less straightforwardly, Pla<strong>to</strong> connects (1) <strong>to</strong> a Heraclitean doctrine of constant<br />

flux. If what a sensible object x is for A is nothing more than how x appears <strong>to</strong><br />

A, <strong>the</strong>n x lacks an intrinsic nature—it is nothing in itself—and hence, in <strong>the</strong><br />

strong sense of ‘being’, x is nothing. Given <strong>the</strong> connection between ‘being’ and<br />

permanence, x also lacks stability and constantly changes. For sensible objects<br />

are continuously changing place so as <strong>to</strong> present different appearances <strong>to</strong><br />

different perceivers.<br />

The refutation of (1) initially attacks <strong>the</strong> relativism and flux doctrines which it<br />

is said <strong>to</strong> imply. Of several objections raised against Protagoras, <strong>the</strong> main<br />

difficulty is that his position is self-refuting. Protagoras’ ‘Man is <strong>the</strong> measure’<br />

doctrine was not that it appears <strong>to</strong> Protagoras that what appears <strong>to</strong> any person A<br />

is for A, but that, absolutely, what appears <strong>to</strong> A is for A. But most people reject<br />

this, that is, for most people it appears that it is not <strong>the</strong> case that what appears <strong>to</strong><br />

A is for A. So if what appears <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m is for <strong>the</strong>m, Protagoras’ doctrine does not<br />

hold for <strong>the</strong>m. Protagoras’ absolute claim is false.<br />

As for <strong>the</strong> flux doctrine, if everything continuously changes in every respect,<br />

no object can be accurately called anything since ‘it is always slipping away<br />

while one is speaking’. So nothing we might call ‘perception’ is any more<br />

perception than not perception, and <strong>the</strong>refore, on <strong>the</strong> proposed definition of<br />

knowledge, nothing is any more knowledge than not knowledge. 61<br />

Finally, Pla<strong>to</strong> attacks <strong>the</strong> definition directly by arguing that no perception can<br />

ever be an instance of knowledge. The argument has aroused much interest

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!