04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

122 PYTHAGOREANS AND ELEATICS<br />

contradiction, but this is not evident at <strong>the</strong> start; it has <strong>to</strong> be shown by argument.<br />

Once that has been done, <strong>the</strong> way that says ‘necessarily, it is’ is <strong>the</strong> only<br />

remaining possibility. Accordingly, it is accepted as true by elimination, and its<br />

consequences examined.<br />

What <strong>the</strong>n is meant here by ‘it is’ and ‘it is not’? First, what is ‘it’? In <strong>the</strong><br />

Greek, <strong>the</strong> verb esti stands alone, as Greek verbs can, without even a pronoun <strong>to</strong><br />

function as <strong>the</strong> grammatical subject. But unless Parmenides is making some<br />

radical and improbable departure from ordinary practice, an intended subject of<br />

discourse, of which ‘is’ and ‘is not’ are here said, must have been meant <strong>to</strong> be<br />

readily supplied from <strong>the</strong> context. Unfortunately for us, <strong>the</strong> original context is<br />

now partly missing. Between <strong>the</strong> promise of <strong>the</strong> goddess and <strong>the</strong> statement of <strong>the</strong><br />

two ways, some now lost stretch of text, probably not long, once s<strong>to</strong>od. None <strong>the</strong><br />

less, what remains is sufficient for near-certainty as <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> intended subject.<br />

The ways are ‘ways of enquiry’. An enquiry, <strong>the</strong>n, is presupposed as being<br />

already afoot. What that enquiry is concerned with, is likely <strong>to</strong> be what <strong>the</strong> first<br />

part of <strong>the</strong> goddess’s promise is concerned with: reality. It is true that <strong>the</strong> word<br />

alē<strong>the</strong>iē nowhere appears subsequently in <strong>the</strong> subject place attached <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

esti. In <strong>the</strong> exploration of <strong>the</strong> true way that says ‘it is’, <strong>the</strong> subject of ‘is’ appears<br />

sometimes, cloaked in <strong>the</strong> unspecific designation (<strong>to</strong>) eon, ‘that which is’. This<br />

phrase, though, can be taken without artificiality as ano<strong>the</strong>r, and metrically more<br />

convenient, way of referring <strong>to</strong> alē<strong>the</strong>iē. (So taken, it involves a metaphysical<br />

pun: see below on <strong>the</strong> meanings of <strong>the</strong> verb einai.)<br />

This conclusion, that alē<strong>the</strong>iē, in <strong>the</strong> sense of ‘reality’, is <strong>the</strong> intended subject,<br />

is central <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> interpretation of Parmenides <strong>to</strong> be presented here. 9 It has been<br />

reached by a simple yet powerful argument. It has yet <strong>to</strong> be subjected, though, <strong>to</strong><br />

a series of severe tests. A reconstruction of Parmenides deserves acceptance only<br />

if it makes convincing sense of <strong>the</strong> whole of <strong>the</strong> surviving evidence.<br />

The first test arises immediately. Can one make sense of an initial choice<br />

between ‘necessarily, reality is’ and ‘necessarily, reality is not’? At this point, we<br />

must also ask about <strong>the</strong> possible meanings of <strong>the</strong> verb einai (‘be’).<br />

In general, it seems <strong>to</strong> make sense, whatever x may be, if one is making an<br />

enquiry in<strong>to</strong> x, <strong>to</strong> start by asking ‘is <strong>the</strong>re any such thing as x or not?’ The<br />

normal usage of <strong>the</strong> verb einai easily covers such a sense of ‘is’. In launching an<br />

enquiry in<strong>to</strong> alē<strong>the</strong>iē, unders<strong>to</strong>od in extension from Homeric usage in a ‘summed<br />

sense’, as what would be jointly indicated by all true statements, Parmenides is in<br />

effect asking, sceptically, ‘why do we have <strong>to</strong> suppose that <strong>the</strong>re is any such<br />

thing in <strong>the</strong> first place?’<br />

Since this entirely normal and familiar use of einai fits <strong>the</strong> context so well,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no need at <strong>the</strong> outset <strong>to</strong> look for more exotic possibilities. 10 Later, though,<br />

when <strong>the</strong> subject of discourse is referred <strong>to</strong> as ‘that which is’ (<strong>to</strong> eon), a different<br />

use of <strong>the</strong> verb bears <strong>the</strong> logical weight. Ano<strong>the</strong>r common use of einai is that in<br />

which it means (said of possible states of affairs) ‘obtain, be <strong>the</strong> case’. If alē<strong>the</strong>iē<br />

is thought of as a ‘summed state of affairs’, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>to</strong> say that <strong>the</strong>re actually exists<br />

such a thing is just <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>to</strong> say that it is <strong>the</strong> case.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!