04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

204 ANAXAGORAS AND THE ATOMISTS<br />

Anaxagoras; consequently <strong>the</strong>ir properties could not be observed, but had <strong>to</strong> be<br />

assigned <strong>to</strong> those individuals by <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory had <strong>to</strong> account for an assumed infinity of phenomena, it<br />

assumed an infinite number of primary substances, while postulating <strong>the</strong><br />

minimum range of explana<strong>to</strong>ry properties, specifically shape, size, spatial<br />

ordering and orientation within a given ordering. All observable bodies are<br />

aggregates of basic substances, which must <strong>the</strong>refore be <strong>to</strong>o small <strong>to</strong> be<br />

perceived. These corpuscles are physically indivisible (a<strong>to</strong>mon, literally<br />

‘uncuttable’), not merely in fact but in principle; Aris<strong>to</strong>tle reports an (unsound)<br />

a<strong>to</strong>mistic argument, which has some affinities with one of Zeno’s arguments<br />

against plurality, that if. (as for example Anaxagoras maintained) it were<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretically possible <strong>to</strong> divide a material thing ad infinitum, <strong>the</strong> division must<br />

reduce <strong>the</strong> thing <strong>to</strong> nothing. This Zenonian argument was supported by ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

for <strong>the</strong> same conclusion; a<strong>to</strong>ms are <strong>the</strong>oretically indivisible because <strong>the</strong>y contain<br />

no void. On this conception bodies split along <strong>the</strong>ir interstices; hence where <strong>the</strong>re<br />

are no interstices, as in an a<strong>to</strong>m, no splitting is possible. (The same principle<br />

accounts for <strong>the</strong> immunity of <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>ms <strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r kinds of change, such as<br />

reshaping, compression and expansion; all require displacement of matter within<br />

an a<strong>to</strong>m, which is impossible without any gaps <strong>to</strong> receive <strong>the</strong> displaced matter.)<br />

It is tempting <strong>to</strong> connect <strong>the</strong> assumption that bodies split only along <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

interstices with <strong>the</strong> Principle of Sufficient Reason, which <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>mists appealed<br />

<strong>to</strong> as a fundamental principle of explanation (arguing for example that <strong>the</strong><br />

number of a<strong>to</strong>mic shapes must be infinite, because <strong>the</strong>re is no more reason for an<br />

a<strong>to</strong>m <strong>to</strong> have one shape than ano<strong>the</strong>r (Simplicius, Physics 28.9–10, DK 67 A 8)).<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal uniformity of an a<strong>to</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>y may have thought, <strong>the</strong>re could be no<br />

reason why it should split at any point, or in any direction, ra<strong>the</strong>r than any o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

Hence by <strong>the</strong> Principle of Sufficient Reason, it could not split at all.<br />

A<strong>to</strong>ms are in a state of eternal motion in empty space; <strong>the</strong> motion is not <strong>the</strong><br />

product of design, but is determined by an infinite series of prior a<strong>to</strong>mic<br />

interactions (whence two of Aris<strong>to</strong>tle’s principle criticisms of Democritus, that<br />

he eliminated final causation and made all a<strong>to</strong>mic motion ‘unnatural’). Empty<br />

space was postulated as required for motion, but was characterized as ‘what is not’,<br />

thus violating <strong>the</strong> Eleatic principle that what is not cannot be. We have no<br />

evidence of how <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>mists met <strong>the</strong> accusation of outright self-contradiction.<br />

As well as explaining <strong>the</strong> possibility of motion, <strong>the</strong> void was postulated <strong>to</strong><br />

account for <strong>the</strong> observed plurality of things, since <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>mists followed<br />

Parmenides (fragment 8, 22–5) in maintaining that <strong>the</strong>re could not be many<br />

things if <strong>the</strong>re were no void <strong>to</strong> separate <strong>the</strong>m. The <strong>the</strong>oretical role of <strong>the</strong> void in<br />

accounting for <strong>the</strong> separation of a<strong>to</strong>ms from one ano<strong>the</strong>r has an interesting<br />

implication, recorded by Philoponus (Physics 494.19–25 (not in DK), On<br />

Generation and Corruption 158.26–159.7, DK 67 A 7). Since a<strong>to</strong>ms are<br />

separated from one ano<strong>the</strong>r by <strong>the</strong> void, <strong>the</strong>y can never strictly speaking come<br />

in<strong>to</strong> contact with one ano<strong>the</strong>r. For if <strong>the</strong>y did, even momentarily, <strong>the</strong>re would be<br />

nothing separating <strong>the</strong>m from one ano<strong>the</strong>r. But <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y would be as inseparable

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!