04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

EMPEDOCLES 167<br />

To illustrate <strong>the</strong> possibility of <strong>the</strong> wide diversity of phenomena generated from<br />

just four elements Empedocles used <strong>the</strong> simile of a painting, which can show in<br />

two dimensions a variety of plant, animal and human life, although it consists<br />

basically of pigments of a few primary colours in a particular arrangement:<br />

As painters, men well taught by wisdom in <strong>the</strong> practice of <strong>the</strong>ir art,<br />

decorate temple offerings when <strong>the</strong>y take in <strong>the</strong>ir hands pigments of various<br />

colours, and after fitting <strong>the</strong>m in close combination—more of some and<br />

less of o<strong>the</strong>rs—<strong>the</strong>y produce from <strong>the</strong>m shapes resembling all things,<br />

creating trees and men and women, animals and birds and water-nourished<br />

fish, and long-lived gods <strong>to</strong>o, highest in honour; so do not let error<br />

convince you that <strong>the</strong>re is any o<strong>the</strong>r source for <strong>the</strong> countless perishables<br />

that are seen…<br />

(fr. 23.1–10)<br />

This fragment also throws light on how parts of elements are placed <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r in a<br />

compound. Empedocles is not speaking of a complete fusion, like blue and<br />

yellow blending <strong>to</strong> form green, but, according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> common practice in Greek<br />

painting, of <strong>the</strong> juxtaposition of pigments or washes (usually black, white, red<br />

and yellow) <strong>to</strong> produce <strong>the</strong> effect of figures and objects. The parts of elements<br />

involved in a compound may be very small, as when for example <strong>the</strong>y form <strong>the</strong><br />

alternating channels of fire and water in <strong>the</strong> eye, or are compared <strong>to</strong> metals<br />

ground down <strong>to</strong> fine powders, but even so <strong>the</strong>y are not reducible <strong>to</strong> absolute<br />

minima. In positing elements in Aris<strong>to</strong>tle’s phrase (On <strong>the</strong> Heavens 305a4) that<br />

are ‘divisible but never going <strong>to</strong> be divided’, Empedocles’ philosophy here<br />

contrasts on <strong>the</strong> one hand with <strong>the</strong> complete infinite divisibility of compounds in<br />

Anaxagoras’ <strong>the</strong>ory and on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r with Democritean a<strong>to</strong>mism.<br />

Empedocles’ far-reaching conclusion that despite appearances <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> contrary<br />

all animate and inanimate forms should be unders<strong>to</strong>od as particular arrangements<br />

in different proportions of a small number of unchanging, qualitatively distinct<br />

elements immediately became standard, and was taken in<strong>to</strong> account by<br />

philosophers, cosmologists, natural scientists and medical writers throughout<br />

antiquity, and in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages and beyond. As a basic principle it<br />

foreshadows contemporary assumptions in a number of areas, for example that<br />

<strong>the</strong> main ingredients of living things are <strong>the</strong> elements of carbon, hydrogen and<br />

oxygen, that language, literature and ma<strong>the</strong>matics can be expressed as encoded<br />

variations of <strong>the</strong> binary numbers zero and one, and that <strong>the</strong> genetic range of<br />

species is reducible <strong>to</strong> an arrangement of <strong>the</strong> four basic letters of <strong>the</strong> DNA<br />

strings.<br />

Some fur<strong>the</strong>r motive force however was required in Empedocles’ scheme <strong>to</strong><br />

explain how <strong>the</strong> four elements come in<strong>to</strong> compounds and separate in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

masses. For this role he posited opposed principles of attraction and repulsion<br />

which, in his vivid vocabulary, he called philia (‘love’, ‘friendship’) and neikos<br />

(‘strife’, ‘hate’). As <strong>the</strong> visible masses of earth, sea, sun and sky had provided

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!