04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

PLATO: AESTHETICS AND PSYCHOLOGY 399<br />

The Soul in O<strong>the</strong>r Dialogues<br />

One question which is likely <strong>to</strong> occur <strong>to</strong> any reader of <strong>the</strong> Phaedo is why, if <strong>the</strong><br />

soul’s true place is outside <strong>the</strong> body, it is ever incarnated in <strong>the</strong> first place, and<br />

especially if everything in <strong>the</strong> world is for <strong>the</strong> best. An answer, which emerges<br />

from <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus and <strong>the</strong> Timaeus, is just that <strong>the</strong> scheme of things demands<br />

living things, and living things require souls <strong>to</strong> animate <strong>the</strong>m. 25 In both<br />

dialogues, <strong>the</strong>se souls have three parts: one higher and rational, and two<br />

irrational, respectively responsible for <strong>the</strong> higher and <strong>the</strong> lower emotions. In <strong>the</strong><br />

Timaeus, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ry of <strong>the</strong> creation represents <strong>the</strong> first and immortal pan as being<br />

created by <strong>the</strong> divine craftsman out of <strong>the</strong> same stuff as <strong>the</strong> soul of <strong>the</strong> universe,<br />

while <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two are <strong>the</strong> products of lesser divinities, specifically <strong>to</strong> meet <strong>the</strong><br />

requirements of bodily existence (<strong>to</strong> survive, we shall need, for example, an<br />

impulse <strong>to</strong> assert and defend ourselves, and a desire <strong>to</strong> take in food and drink). 26<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus, <strong>the</strong> three parts are compared <strong>to</strong> a charioteer and his two horses,<br />

one his natural ally, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r—<strong>the</strong> lusting, lecherous one—in permanent<br />

opposition <strong>to</strong> him; but unlike normal chariot teams, this one, including <strong>the</strong><br />

charioteer, is a single whole, ‘grown <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r’. 27 Out of <strong>the</strong> body, <strong>the</strong> most<br />

fortunate souls will be able <strong>to</strong> control <strong>the</strong>ir horses, and will join <strong>the</strong> gods, if only<br />

temporarily, <strong>to</strong> feast on reality and truth; in it, <strong>the</strong>y will struggle against <strong>the</strong> lusts<br />

of <strong>the</strong> second horse <strong>to</strong> regain <strong>the</strong>ir memories of <strong>the</strong> feast.<br />

This opposition between <strong>the</strong> highest and lowest parts is a fundamental feature<br />

of <strong>the</strong> tripartite model of <strong>the</strong> soul. It expresses what <strong>the</strong> Phaedo describes in terms<br />

of <strong>the</strong> opposition between soul and body, <strong>the</strong> ‘lower’ desires being precisely<br />

those which are <strong>the</strong>re treated as belonging <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> body itself. Pla<strong>to</strong>’s basic<br />

position is in a way bipartite ra<strong>the</strong>r than tripartite; that is, in so far as he sees <strong>the</strong><br />

human soul as a battleground between <strong>the</strong> rational, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and <strong>the</strong><br />

irrational or ‘bodily’ on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The rational part is as it were <strong>the</strong> ‘eye’ of <strong>the</strong><br />

soul, which will ‘see’ <strong>the</strong> truth, on two conditions: first, that it is itself fully<br />

developed; and second, that it is not prevented from doing so by <strong>the</strong> irrational in<br />

us. 28 This is <strong>the</strong> view which underlies <strong>the</strong> Phaedo, and it is also what we find in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Laws. But elsewhere we find <strong>the</strong> more complex tripartite model, which<br />

recognizes that some aspects of <strong>the</strong> irrational are not only necessary for our<br />

survival, but can contribute positively <strong>to</strong>wards <strong>the</strong> good life. By splitting <strong>the</strong><br />

irrational element in<strong>to</strong> two parts, one of which is <strong>the</strong> natural ‘ally’ of reason,<br />

while <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r tends <strong>to</strong> disrupt it, Pla<strong>to</strong> is able <strong>to</strong> make this concession while<br />

still maintaining <strong>the</strong> sense of a basic opposition between rational and irrational.<br />

However he also has independent grounds for this move. In Book IV of <strong>the</strong><br />

Republic, he has Socrates argue at considerable length for <strong>the</strong> existence of three<br />

soul-parts. (In fact, Socrates introduces <strong>the</strong> term ‘part’ only with considerable<br />

hesitation: at first he prefers eidos, ‘kind of thing’, ethos, ‘character-type’, or<br />

plain ‘something’, as in, for example, tri<strong>to</strong>n ti, ‘a third something’ (435bff.). But<br />

<strong>the</strong> Phaedrus and <strong>the</strong> Timaeus show no such reluctance, and <strong>the</strong> Timaeus actually<br />

locates <strong>the</strong> three parts in separate parts of <strong>the</strong> body.) Socrates has argued that <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!