04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 127<br />

The ‘signs’ are best taken as <strong>the</strong> proofs, <strong>to</strong> follow, of <strong>the</strong> properties announced<br />

here as belonging <strong>to</strong> ‘what is’ (eon), i.e. reality. Evidently <strong>the</strong> deduction of <strong>the</strong><br />

consequences of ‘it is’ constitutes, as expected, <strong>the</strong> journey along <strong>the</strong> way.<br />

(a)<br />

Reality cannot come-<strong>to</strong>-be nor cease-<strong>to</strong>-be (B 8.6–21)<br />

For, what origin will you seek for it? How and from where did it<br />

grow? Nor will I let you say or think that [it did so] out of what is<br />

not, for it is not sayable or thinkable that it is not. Besides, what<br />

necessity would have driven it on <strong>to</strong> come-<strong>to</strong>-be, later or sooner,<br />

starting from what is not?<br />

(DK 28 B 8.6–10)<br />

The first section of proof reveals <strong>the</strong> techniques of argument characteristic of this<br />

part. For convenience, <strong>the</strong> subject (‘what is’ or ‘reality’) will be denoted by E.<br />

Suppose that E does at some time come-<strong>to</strong>-be. Then Parmenides asks: out of what<br />

does it come-<strong>to</strong>-be? The implied premiss is: (10) whatever comes-<strong>to</strong>-be, comes<strong>to</strong>-be<br />

out of something. Parmenides seems <strong>to</strong> have taken (10) as self-evidently<br />

true; it is plausible <strong>to</strong> connect it with o<strong>the</strong>r places in this argument where he<br />

seems <strong>to</strong> have some variety of <strong>the</strong> Principle of Sufficient Reason in mind.<br />

So, if E comes-<strong>to</strong>-be, it comes-<strong>to</strong>-be out of F (say). Then for F, in turn, <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

<strong>the</strong> two possibilities: F is, or F is not. Parmenides considers <strong>the</strong> second<br />

possibility, but not, apparently, <strong>the</strong> first one. This is a first problem.<br />

There is an extra twist <strong>to</strong> it. So far, we have considered Parmenides’ reasonings<br />

about ‘it is’ and ‘it is not’ without taking account of <strong>the</strong> ambiguities of <strong>the</strong><br />

present tense. The rejection of <strong>the</strong> way ‘it is not’ does not call for <strong>the</strong>se <strong>to</strong> be<br />

considered. But <strong>the</strong> Greek present tense is ambiguous in <strong>the</strong> same ways as <strong>the</strong><br />

English one; and where, as here, possible past and future events are being<br />

discussed, it becomes necessary <strong>to</strong> distinguish <strong>the</strong> various uses. ‘It is’ and ‘it is<br />

not’ may be timeless, or refer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> coming-<strong>to</strong>-be, or <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> time of<br />

utterance, if that is different. Parmenides gives us no help at all on this point; but<br />

it is plausible <strong>to</strong> assume that he means <strong>the</strong> question ‘is F or is it not?’ <strong>to</strong> be<br />

unders<strong>to</strong>od as specialized (in line with ordinary usage) <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> time of coming-<strong>to</strong>be.<br />

This results, as will now be shown, in an intelligible argument.<br />

The question is <strong>the</strong>n: E comes-<strong>to</strong>-be out of F; is F, or is it not, at <strong>the</strong> time of<br />

E’s coming-<strong>to</strong>-be? First, if F is, at that time, <strong>the</strong>n at that time it is part of E, since<br />

E (on <strong>the</strong> interpretation followed here) is <strong>the</strong> whole of reality. But nothing can<br />

come-<strong>to</strong>-be out of a part of itself, since that does not count as coming-<strong>to</strong>-be at<br />

all. This point will account for Parmenides’ failure <strong>to</strong> examine <strong>the</strong> supposition ‘F<br />

is’.<br />

Second, suppose <strong>the</strong>n that F, at <strong>the</strong> time of E’s coming-<strong>to</strong>-be, is not. This is<br />

<strong>the</strong> case which Parmenides examines. He gives two arguments.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!