04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 243<br />

be given as <strong>to</strong> what is x?’ above all when x is a moral or political concept. This<br />

became famous as <strong>the</strong> Socratic method of Elenchos, and this alone would be<br />

sufficient <strong>to</strong> justify us in considering him as an active member of <strong>the</strong> Sophistic<br />

Movement, in fact as an unpaid sophist.<br />

In addition <strong>to</strong> named sophists it is necessary <strong>to</strong> discuss a number of<br />

anonymous sophistic writings, of which several survive, at least in summary<br />

form. The first of <strong>the</strong>se is known as <strong>the</strong> Dissoi Logoi, <strong>the</strong> title being taken from<br />

<strong>the</strong> first two words of <strong>the</strong> opening paragraph, which are repeated in <strong>the</strong> next three<br />

chapters. The text is found at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> main manuscripts of Sextus<br />

Empiricus, and it is written in a dialect which is a form of literary Doric. This<br />

has suggested <strong>to</strong> some that it may have originated in Sicily or sou<strong>the</strong>rn Italy, but<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no o<strong>the</strong>r positive evidence for this. It has commonly been supposed that<br />

it was composed soon after 400 BC on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> reference in I.8–10 (DK<br />

90) where <strong>the</strong> vic<strong>to</strong>ry which <strong>the</strong> Spartans won over <strong>the</strong> A<strong>the</strong>nians and <strong>the</strong>ir allies<br />

is spoken as a most recent event. But this dating is quite uncertain and o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

have argued for a much later date.<br />

The pattern of arguments followed throughout <strong>the</strong> treatise is established in <strong>the</strong><br />

first chapter where we are <strong>to</strong>ld that ‘some say that good is one thing and bad is<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r thing, while o<strong>the</strong>rs say that <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> same, and that for <strong>the</strong> same<br />

person it is on one occasion good and on ano<strong>the</strong>r occasion bad.’ This formulation<br />

is potentially ambiguous. On one view <strong>to</strong> say that good and bad are <strong>the</strong> same<br />

thing might be taken <strong>to</strong> say that <strong>the</strong> two terms are identical in meaning, or it<br />

might mean that any one thing will be both good and bad ei<strong>the</strong>r simultaneously or<br />

at different times and in different relationships. It is however <strong>the</strong> second<br />

interpretation which should be preferred: <strong>the</strong> meanings of <strong>the</strong> two terms are<br />

always different and it is <strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>to</strong> be applied as attributes <strong>to</strong><br />

particular things or situations which varies. What we are explicitly <strong>to</strong>ld is that as<br />

<strong>the</strong> name or term used differs so does <strong>the</strong> thing. This is repeated three times in<br />

subsequent sections, in one of which (II.1) ‘thing’ is expressed by sōma or<br />

physical body. There seems no doubt that what we are being confronted with is<br />

<strong>the</strong> familiar sophistic problem of varying predicates attached <strong>to</strong> physical objects<br />

in <strong>the</strong> external world. The whole approach of <strong>the</strong> Dissoi Logoi amounts <strong>to</strong> an<br />

application of <strong>the</strong> sophistic doctrine of relativism. After good and bad in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

section <strong>the</strong> same treatment is applied <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> terms for beautiful and ugly, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>to</strong><br />

just and unjust, <strong>the</strong> truth and falsehood of propositions, and <strong>the</strong> question of <strong>the</strong><br />

teachability or o<strong>the</strong>rwise of wisdom and virtue. After <strong>the</strong> discussion of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

terms <strong>the</strong> treatise concludes with arguments that election by lot is a bad method<br />

of election in democracies, that <strong>the</strong> art of <strong>the</strong> man who is skilled in argument<br />

(and so has been trained by a sophist) is <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> art of <strong>the</strong> statesman, and<br />

that a developed use of memory is essential for intellectual wisdom and its<br />

application in <strong>the</strong> conduct of human affairs.<br />

A second anonymous treatise is known as <strong>the</strong> Anonymus lamblichi. This was<br />

identified in 1889 when Friedrich Blass showed that some ten pages of printed<br />

Greek text in <strong>the</strong> Protrepticus of Iamblichus were taken apparently virtually

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!