04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

406 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

of mimēsis. Because mimētai (now including <strong>the</strong> poet) are not dealing with<br />

reality, or how things really are, <strong>the</strong>y must inevitably relate <strong>to</strong> how things appear<br />

<strong>to</strong> be. People say that in order <strong>to</strong> write well, poets must know <strong>the</strong> truth, but in<br />

fact <strong>the</strong>y do not. If <strong>the</strong>y did, <strong>the</strong>y would not be satisfied with recreating mere<br />

images (mere surface views of things), but would prefer <strong>to</strong> try <strong>to</strong> recreate <strong>the</strong> real<br />

thing: thus if Homer really knew about medicine, he would have been a doc<strong>to</strong>r,<br />

and if he knew anything about virtue, he would have been a lawgiver ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

a poet. 55 This is <strong>the</strong> route by which we reach <strong>the</strong> conclusion about ‘all poets’,<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y are ‘mimētai of images of virtue’, without grasping <strong>the</strong> truth, for if <strong>the</strong>y<br />

do in any way represent good men in <strong>the</strong>ir poetry, saying and doing ‘virtuous’<br />

things, it cannot be because of <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge of virtue itself. But <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong><br />

techniques which enable <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> convince anyone else who is ignorant 56 that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y do know something.<br />

Then, after ano<strong>the</strong>r piece of persuasive description 57 <strong>to</strong> establish <strong>the</strong> poets’<br />

lack of knowledge, we reach <strong>the</strong> last stage of <strong>the</strong> argument. If mimēsis operates<br />

at third remove from <strong>the</strong> truth, Socrates asks, <strong>to</strong> which aspect of <strong>the</strong> human being<br />

does it direct itself? Things may appear <strong>to</strong> have different shapes and sizes from<br />

<strong>the</strong> ones <strong>the</strong>y really have (so, for example, a stick will appear bent if seen<br />

through water); in such cases, reason tells us one thing, which is contradicted by<br />

appearances. If we use <strong>the</strong> principle we used before, in <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> soul, that<br />

<strong>the</strong> same thing cannot act or be acted upon in opposite ways at <strong>the</strong> same time,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it follows that <strong>the</strong> part 58 of <strong>the</strong> soul which thinks things are o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>y<br />

really are must be different from <strong>the</strong> one that ‘relies on measure and calculation’<br />

(603a), which is of course <strong>the</strong> best, reasoning or calculating, part; it must<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore be one of <strong>the</strong> low-grade 59 parts. So any sort of art concerned with<br />

mimēsis (so, again, poetry <strong>to</strong>o) will be a low-grade sort of mistress, consorting<br />

with <strong>the</strong> low-grade.<br />

There are some problems here: it looks as if we shall need some subrational<br />

part which is never<strong>the</strong>less capable of having beliefs (e.g. that ‘this stick is bent’),<br />

and nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> ‘spirited‘ nor <strong>the</strong> appetitive part, from descriptions of <strong>the</strong>m in<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r contexts, looks particularly well suited for having this capacity. In that case,<br />

we shall need an extra ‘part’ of <strong>the</strong> soul, which is different both from <strong>the</strong> part<br />

that is reasoning or calculating successfully, and from both of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parts<br />

which were argued for in Book IV. In <strong>the</strong> event, when he comes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> question<br />

of which aspect of <strong>the</strong> mind 60 is affected by poetry, Socrates at first avoids<br />

identifying it with ei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>se original two lower parts, and again simply talks<br />

about something which is different from what is best, though it does also take on<br />

<strong>the</strong> features of an individual: ‘as for <strong>the</strong> part which draws us <strong>to</strong>wards<br />

recollections of our suffering and <strong>to</strong>wards lamentations, and is insatiable for <strong>the</strong>se<br />

—shan’t we say that it is unreasoning, and lazy, and fond of cowardice?’ (604d).<br />

Eventually, however, when he passes on <strong>to</strong> what he calls ‘<strong>the</strong> greatest charge’<br />

against poetry (that it can corrupt even <strong>the</strong> best), he comes clean: ‘And in relation<br />

<strong>to</strong> sex, <strong>to</strong>o, and anger, and all those aspects of <strong>the</strong> soul which have <strong>to</strong> do with desire<br />

and pain and pleasure, 61 which we say accompany every action, it’s <strong>the</strong> case that

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!