04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 337<br />

As <strong>the</strong> goal of a passionate longing, <strong>the</strong> Forms are objects of desire, and <strong>to</strong><br />

‘acquire’ <strong>the</strong>m by knowing <strong>the</strong>m is a mystical experience of divine 19 beings. All<br />

people, most unconsciously, yearn <strong>to</strong> recapture <strong>the</strong> vision of <strong>the</strong> Forms which<br />

<strong>the</strong>y enjoyed before birth. This alone did give <strong>the</strong>m and would give <strong>the</strong>m<br />

complete satisfaction and happiness.<br />

All this makes some sense only if <strong>the</strong> Forms are perfect paradigms. Because of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir greater reality ‘possession’ of <strong>the</strong> Forms gives true satisfaction in a way in<br />

which possession of sensibles does not. And part of that greater reality consists<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Forms being perfectly what sensible objects are only deficiently or in<br />

appearance.<br />

Similarly, Forms are more real because of <strong>the</strong>ir greater ‘cognitive visibility’ in<br />

comparison with sensible objects. 20 If we want <strong>to</strong> learn what a property F is, <strong>the</strong><br />

observation of a sensible F will typically prove of little use since <strong>the</strong> property<br />

will be bound up with its opposite, and so <strong>the</strong> observation will provide a<br />

confused idea of what F-ness is. However, if we could attain a clear view of <strong>the</strong><br />

Form we would immediately know what F-ness is because it is a ‘pure’ and<br />

perfect example of F uncontaminated by its opposite (cf. Philebus 44d–45a).<br />

Here again, <strong>the</strong> greater reality of <strong>the</strong> Forms depends on <strong>the</strong>ir being paradigms.<br />

Self-predication, <strong>the</strong>n, is fundamental for Pla<strong>to</strong>’s philosophy. However, it is a<br />

mistake, arising, in part, from confusions that helped <strong>to</strong> make it seem entirely<br />

natural.<br />

1 Pla<strong>to</strong> does not distinguish different uses of ‘<strong>to</strong> be.’ His single Form of Being<br />

merges <strong>the</strong>se different uses with <strong>the</strong> features of true being noted before. So<br />

<strong>the</strong> existential use is run <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> identifying use, 21 <strong>the</strong> existential<br />

use is conflated with <strong>the</strong> predicative use, 22 and <strong>the</strong> predicative use is<br />

confused with <strong>the</strong> identifying use. 23 Given <strong>the</strong> last confusion, since, plainly,<br />

Beauty is Beauty, it may also seem self-evident that Beauty is beautiful.<br />

2 Pre-Socratic philosophers did not always properly distinguish between<br />

objects and properties. Thus, Anaxagoras spoke of ‘<strong>the</strong> hot’ and ‘<strong>the</strong> cold’<br />

on a par with ‘earth’ as elements from which things come <strong>to</strong> be. If Pla<strong>to</strong> <strong>to</strong>o<br />

was not clear on this point, <strong>the</strong>n it would have been natural for him <strong>to</strong> think<br />

of Beauty as a beautiful object. 24<br />

The point is not that Pla<strong>to</strong> did not distinguish attributes and objects but<br />

that he did not adequately distinguish <strong>the</strong> kinds of thing which <strong>the</strong>y are.<br />

3 Greek uses expressions formed from <strong>the</strong> definite article and an adjective<br />

such as ‘<strong>the</strong> beautiful’ <strong>to</strong> name properties. Occasionally Pla<strong>to</strong> will even use<br />

<strong>the</strong> adjective on its own as <strong>the</strong> subject of a sentence <strong>to</strong> refer <strong>to</strong> a Form. Such<br />

expressions lend <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>to</strong> being unders<strong>to</strong>od as operating in <strong>the</strong> same<br />

manner in which <strong>the</strong>y do operate when applied <strong>to</strong> sensible individuals, namely<br />

as describing <strong>the</strong> object named. And this danger is especially serious in<br />

Pla<strong>to</strong>’s case for (Cratylus 384d–385c) he does not adequately distinguish<br />

naming and describing. So he could easily understand terms designating <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!