04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

PLATO: AESTHETICS AND PSYCHOLOGY 413<br />

16 Although <strong>the</strong> Phaedo does include talk of <strong>the</strong> desires etc. ‘of <strong>the</strong> body’, it is<br />

unlikely that we should take this at face value. Without soul <strong>to</strong> bring life <strong>to</strong> it, <strong>the</strong><br />

body is merely inert matter, and unable ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> do or <strong>to</strong> feel anything.<br />

17 The issue arises specifically in relation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> third argument for immortality, <strong>the</strong><br />

so-called ‘affinity’ argument: see Rowe [12.18] and [12.2], 189.<br />

18 In so far as that content would be memorable, in a Pla<strong>to</strong>nic world, it would be true;<br />

but in that case it would not distinguish any one excellent soul from ano<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

19 The chief difference will be that in <strong>the</strong> one case <strong>the</strong> soul can evidently lose its<br />

irrationality al<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r, while in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r it must permanently retain it— if<br />

irrationality is part of its essence. Yet a soul which is both out of a body and has<br />

been trained <strong>to</strong> separate itself from ‘bodily influences’ might perhaps be said <strong>to</strong><br />

have irrational elements only potentially, and <strong>the</strong>n only if it is bound <strong>to</strong> be<br />

reincarnated. It might be partly this that Pla<strong>to</strong> has in mind when in <strong>the</strong> Timaeus he<br />

calls <strong>the</strong> two lower parts ‘mortal’ (69e).<br />

20 Republic 498d suggests that arguments heard in a previous life might affect a soul<br />

in a subsequent one; and evidently, if what was a human soul passes in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> body<br />

of a donkey, that must have something <strong>to</strong> do with what that soul had become in its<br />

previous occupation of a body (i.e. donkey-like). But nei<strong>the</strong>r that soul nor any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

will have any evidence <strong>to</strong> connect it with <strong>the</strong> earlier human person; it cannot even<br />

be inferred that Ned (<strong>the</strong> donkey) was previously Fred (a man), since donkeys’<br />

souls may presumably also have previously animated donkeys.<br />

21 Elsewhere (Phaedrus 249b–c) it looks as if Pla<strong>to</strong> may envisage a partial<br />

recollection of <strong>the</strong> Forms, which explains <strong>the</strong> formation of concepts presupposed<br />

by <strong>the</strong> ordinary, everyday use of language; but in <strong>the</strong> Phaedo what is being talked<br />

of is an experience which is evidently restricted <strong>to</strong> philosophers.<br />

22 Phaedrus 246dff. According <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meno (86a), <strong>the</strong> soul is perpetually in a state of<br />

having learned <strong>the</strong> knowledge in question, which seems <strong>to</strong> imply that <strong>the</strong>re never was<br />

a point at which we actually acquired it.<br />

23 In <strong>the</strong> Meno, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of recollection is introduced <strong>to</strong> resolve <strong>the</strong> general question<br />

about how one can look for something one doesn’t know, or recognize it when one<br />

has found it. It is evidently <strong>the</strong> vividness of <strong>the</strong> experience in question, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

with <strong>the</strong> way that what we remember allows things <strong>to</strong> make sense, which is<br />

supposed <strong>to</strong> rule out <strong>the</strong> possibility of false memory.<br />

24 This expression should not be pressed <strong>to</strong>o hard. The Forms, which are <strong>the</strong> objects<br />

of knowledge for <strong>the</strong> soul, are apparently ‘outside’ time and space al<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r;<br />

divine souls (gods), on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, appear <strong>to</strong> be part of <strong>the</strong> natural universe<br />

(except in <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> crea<strong>to</strong>r god of <strong>the</strong> Timaeus—but whe<strong>the</strong>r we are supposed<br />

<strong>to</strong> believe literally in his existence is unclear), which is where all discarnate souls<br />

also seem <strong>to</strong> be located; on death souls simply move <strong>to</strong> some less well-known, but<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less physical, location.<br />

25 An underlying assumption of <strong>the</strong> Timaeus is that if <strong>the</strong> world is as good as it can be,<br />

it cannot be any o<strong>the</strong>r way than it is, and will include all possible types of<br />

creatures.<br />

26 <strong>From</strong> this perspective, <strong>the</strong> description of <strong>the</strong>se two parts as ‘mortal’ (see n. 19)<br />

looks natural enough, in so far as <strong>the</strong>ir presence is a consequence of <strong>the</strong> soul’s<br />

function in relation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> body, and <strong>the</strong> compound of soul and body is itself<br />

mortal. They would be actually mortal if a soul finally and permanently escaped <strong>the</strong><br />

bodily condition.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!