04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

414 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

27 The word is sumphu<strong>to</strong>s (246a).<br />

28 As Johansen points out <strong>to</strong> me, on <strong>the</strong> account in <strong>the</strong> Phaedo it is perhaps only <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of <strong>the</strong> irrational or <strong>the</strong> ‘bodily’ which prevents <strong>the</strong> full flowering of <strong>the</strong><br />

rational soul. But elsewhere, e.g. in <strong>the</strong> Republic, <strong>the</strong> removal of (undue) irrational<br />

influences is only a necessary, not a sufficient, condition of <strong>the</strong> acquisition of<br />

wisdom; training is required, and even if this is translated in<strong>to</strong> terms of anamnēsis,<br />

it is not obviously just a matter of seeing off <strong>the</strong> irrational parts.<br />

29 This is <strong>the</strong> traditional, and unsatisfac<strong>to</strong>ry, English rendering of <strong>the</strong> Greek thumos,<br />

which is connected primarily with anger and indignation.<br />

30 For Pla<strong>to</strong>, what is natural is not what is normally <strong>the</strong> case, but ra<strong>the</strong>r what should<br />

be <strong>the</strong> case, even if it rarely or never is.<br />

31 Spirit, it seems, can and may listen <strong>to</strong> reason, like an animal adapted for<br />

domestication, and yet speaks <strong>the</strong> same language as <strong>the</strong> appetitive part, pitching<br />

emotion (especially shame, <strong>the</strong> reverse side of honour) against emotion. (The<br />

appetitive part is summed up in <strong>the</strong> image of <strong>the</strong> many-headed beast in Republic IX:<br />

even if it has some tame or domesticated heads, it cannot be reliably domesticated<br />

as a whole, only restrained and cut back.) Yet reason <strong>to</strong>o has its own desires (see<br />

later in this section), and if so, it can apparently control <strong>the</strong> appetites directly, by<br />

opposing its own drives <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. In that case, it is not clear why it needs its alliance<br />

with <strong>the</strong> spirited part, however appropriate <strong>the</strong> corresponding idea might be on <strong>the</strong><br />

political level; <strong>the</strong>re reason, in <strong>the</strong> shape of <strong>the</strong> philosopher-rulers, will need a<br />

police force, for fear of being overwhelmed by <strong>the</strong> sheer numbers of <strong>the</strong> lowest<br />

group in society.<br />

32 This analysis, in Books VIII and IX of <strong>the</strong> Republic, may be compared with <strong>the</strong><br />

simpler one at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> Statesman, where <strong>the</strong> king or statesman’s chief role is<br />

identified as <strong>the</strong> weaving <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> more aggressive and competitive type of<br />

citizen with <strong>the</strong> quieter and milder.<br />

33 249d-e. It is in this sort of context that <strong>the</strong> description of Pla<strong>to</strong> as appropriating<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r forms of discourse (see earlier in this section) seems particularly apt: <strong>the</strong><br />

philosopher does everything <strong>the</strong> ordinary lover does (251dff.), but for entirely<br />

different reasons, and his experience is far more fulfilling than anything that<br />

ordinarily goes under <strong>the</strong> heading of erōs or sexual love.<br />

34 The description—in <strong>the</strong> main part of Socrates’ contribution <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> banquet, which he<br />

puts in <strong>the</strong> mouth of <strong>the</strong> imaginary priestess Diotima—is couched in terms of an<br />

initiation, and an initiate would no doubt have had an instruc<strong>to</strong>r. If we see <strong>the</strong><br />

‘ascent of love’ as in part an allegory of a philosophical education, <strong>the</strong> guide will<br />

be <strong>the</strong> master-dialectician (I owe this suggestion <strong>to</strong> Robin Hard).<br />

35 The reasoning part, by contrast, seems <strong>to</strong> be adaptable: it can be corrupted, and be<br />

pressed in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> service of ei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two parts (cf. Republic 587a). On <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility of a different model of <strong>the</strong> relationship between reason and <strong>the</strong><br />

irrational, in <strong>the</strong> Symposium, see especially n. 37 below.<br />

36 Republic 485d; Socrates is here talking of <strong>the</strong> philosopher, and <strong>the</strong> way in which<br />

his preoccupation with ‘<strong>the</strong> pleasure of <strong>the</strong> soul’ will lead him <strong>to</strong> neglect ‘those<br />

through <strong>the</strong> body’, i.e. those which reach <strong>the</strong> soul through <strong>the</strong> senses.<br />

37 It may be objected (and Penner in fact objected) that if Socrates does not introduce<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>pic of tripartition in <strong>the</strong> Symposium, we have no particular justification for<br />

introducing it ourselves, apart from what we think we can derive from conclusions<br />

about <strong>the</strong> relative chronology of <strong>the</strong> dialogues (<strong>the</strong> Symposium is normally

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!