04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

252 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

represents by straight lines. The essential content of <strong>the</strong> definition may be<br />

paraphrased as follows:<br />

V, def. 5. x:y :: z:w if and only if whenever a multiple m·x is greater than<br />

(equal <strong>to</strong> or less than) a multiple n·y, m·z is greater than (equal <strong>to</strong> or less<br />

than) n·w, and (V, def. 7) if for some m and n<br />

and .<br />

Euclid proceeds <strong>to</strong> prove a number of important laws of proportionality, e.g.,<br />

alternation (V.16: if x:y :: z:w, <strong>the</strong>n x:z :: y:w) using a strictly formal reduction<br />

<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition and <strong>to</strong> basic properties of multiplication and size comparison. In<br />

Book VI Euclid applies <strong>the</strong>se laws <strong>to</strong> plane geometric objects.<br />

Geometry disappears at <strong>the</strong> end of Book VI when Euclid turns <strong>to</strong> arithmetic,<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject of VII–IX. Logically <strong>the</strong>se three books are completely independent of<br />

<strong>the</strong> first six. In <strong>the</strong>m Euclid uses a notion of proportionality specific <strong>to</strong> numbers,<br />

i.e., positive integers, and proves for numbers laws of proportionality already<br />

proven for magnitudes in Book V.<br />

In Book X <strong>the</strong>re is a kind of unification of arithmetic and geometry. Euclid<br />

distinguishes between commensurable and incommensurable magnitudes, again<br />

represented by straight lines, and proves:<br />

X.5–8. Two magnitudes are commensurable if and only if <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong><br />

ratio of a number <strong>to</strong> a number.<br />

I shall briefly discuss <strong>the</strong> proof of <strong>the</strong>se propositions at <strong>the</strong> end of section 5, but<br />

in <strong>the</strong> immediate discussion I shall treat this equivalence as something which can<br />

be taken for granted as well known <strong>to</strong> Greek ma<strong>the</strong>maticians of <strong>the</strong> fourth and<br />

perhaps even fifth century. The bulk of Book X is given over <strong>to</strong> an elaborate<br />

classification of certain ‘irrational’ (alogos) straight lines. 4 Euclid proves <strong>the</strong><br />

‘irrationality’ of a number of straight lines, <strong>the</strong> most important being:<br />

<strong>the</strong> medial, <strong>the</strong> side of a square equal <strong>to</strong> a rectangle with incommensurable<br />

‘rational’ sides;<br />

<strong>the</strong> binomial, <strong>the</strong> sum of two incommensurable ‘rational’ straight lines;<br />

<strong>the</strong> apo<strong>to</strong>me, <strong>the</strong> difference of two incommensurable ‘rational’ straight<br />

lines.<br />

Book XI covers a great deal of elementary solid geometry quite rapidly; by<br />

contrast with his procedure in Books I—IV and VI, Euclid appears willing <strong>to</strong> use<br />

proportionality whenever he thinks it simplifies his argumentation. Book XII is<br />

characterized by <strong>the</strong> method used in establishing its principal results, <strong>the</strong> socalled<br />

method of exhaustion. The method of exhaustion is, in fact, a rigorous<br />

technique of indefinitely closer approximations <strong>to</strong> a given magnitude. It depends

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!