04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

372 PLATO: ETHICS AND POLITICS<br />

command whatever spirit or appetite demanded. Yet it is weak, both in that it is<br />

directed by ano<strong>the</strong>r’s, and in that it can lead spirit or appetite only in a direction<br />

in which this is willing <strong>to</strong> go. Their courage or temperance is thus doubly<br />

parasitic: it depends upon a judgement which echoes ano<strong>the</strong>r’s wisdom, and<br />

which only prevails because that wisdom makes sure that it meets no resistance.<br />

Expulsion from Pla<strong>to</strong>’s paradise would be <strong>the</strong> fall of <strong>the</strong>se men: in <strong>the</strong> terms of<br />

<strong>the</strong> rake’s progress that he sketches in Books VIII and IX, auxiliaries would<br />

become timarchic men corrupted by honour, and artisans oligarchic, democratic<br />

or tyrannical men corrupted by pleasure. It is by moral luck that <strong>the</strong>y attain <strong>to</strong><br />

virtue of a kind. They are not fully brave or temperate but wholly unwise; ra<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are brave or temperate in a way through a wisdom that <strong>the</strong>y can accept but<br />

not achieve. The unity of <strong>the</strong> virtues proper is reflected in a unity of popular<br />

virtue.<br />

Thus <strong>the</strong> virtue of individuals is a unitary condition of <strong>the</strong>ir psychic parts. How<br />

is it needed <strong>to</strong> make <strong>the</strong>m happy? The readiest answer <strong>to</strong> this question focuses<br />

upon temperance, which is defined within <strong>the</strong> soul as follows: ‘We call a person<br />

temperate by reason of <strong>the</strong> friendship and harmony of <strong>the</strong>se parts, that is, when<br />

<strong>the</strong> ruler and its two subjects agree that reason ought <strong>to</strong> rule, and do not raise<br />

raise faction against it’ (IV.442c10–d1). Caring for all <strong>the</strong> parts alike, reason<br />

makes <strong>the</strong>m ‘friends’ (IX.589b4–5); parts, like people, will be ‘alike and friends’<br />

if <strong>the</strong>y share <strong>the</strong> same governance (590d5–6). Socrates remarks again that vice is<br />

a sickness of <strong>the</strong> soul (IV.444e1), and can now explain. Eryximachus was giving<br />

fanciful expression <strong>to</strong> a Greek commonplace when he defined it as <strong>the</strong> task of<br />

medicine <strong>to</strong> produce ‘love and concord’ between <strong>the</strong> opposites (hot and cold, wet<br />

and dry, and so forth) that are <strong>the</strong> elements of <strong>the</strong> body (Symposium 186d6–e3).<br />

Mental health is <strong>the</strong> peace of mind that comes of parts of <strong>the</strong> soul that are friends<br />

and not factions. Without temperance, a man is prey <strong>to</strong> conflicting desires,<br />

perhaps subdued but not persuaded, which make him ‘a kind of double<br />

individual’ (Republic VIII.554d9–e1). There is a good and bad slavery: while<br />

reason is a benevolent master who educates desire, <strong>the</strong> appetites are a tyrannical<br />

one who frustrates it (IX.577d1–12). Reason can hope <strong>to</strong> rule with consent because<br />

of its altruism and intelligence. It was <strong>the</strong> soul’s original nature (X.611d7–e3),<br />

and <strong>the</strong> origin of <strong>the</strong> mortal soul (Timaeus 42e7–8); so its attitude is paternalist,<br />

like that of a farmer tending his crops (Republic IX.589b2–3). In indulging<br />

necessary appetites (those we cannot divert, or whose satisfaction benefits us,<br />

VIII.558d9–e2), it keeps appetite content. Being a master of language, it can<br />

‘tame by logos’, persuading and not compelling (554d2). As reason can grasp<br />

appetite’s concept of <strong>the</strong> pleasant, while appetite cannot make out reason’s<br />

concept of <strong>the</strong> good, reason can take appetite by <strong>the</strong> hand, whereas a recalcitrant<br />

appetite could only turn its back on reason.<br />

So translated from <strong>the</strong> outer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner world, from society <strong>to</strong> soul, justice<br />

becomes not a demand but an overriding need. The s<strong>to</strong>ry of Gyges’ ring was a<br />

fable of external accidents; in its internal essence, <strong>the</strong>re is no such thing as

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!