04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

212 ANAXAGORAS AND THE ATOMISTS<br />

provided by <strong>the</strong> intellect (fr. 11). The latter is specifically said <strong>to</strong> be concerned<br />

with things which fall below <strong>the</strong> limits of sensory discrimination, and we must<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore suppose that <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>mic <strong>the</strong>ory itself is <strong>to</strong> be ascribed <strong>to</strong> this form of<br />

knowledge. This is supported by those passages (ibid. VIII.6–7, 56) in which<br />

Sextus associates <strong>the</strong> position of Democritus with that of Pla<strong>to</strong>, in that both<br />

reject <strong>the</strong> senses as sources of knowledge and maintain that only intelligible<br />

things are real; for Pla<strong>to</strong>, of course, <strong>the</strong> intelligible things are <strong>the</strong> Forms, whereas<br />

for Democritus <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>ms, which are inaccessible <strong>to</strong> perception and,<br />

consequently, such that <strong>the</strong>ir properties are determinable only by <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Thus far <strong>the</strong> prospects for a unified interpretation of Democritus’<br />

epistemology look promising. The position expressed in <strong>the</strong> fragments cited by<br />

Sextus is not general scepticism, but what we might term <strong>the</strong>oretical realism. The<br />

character of <strong>the</strong> physical world is nei<strong>the</strong>r revealed by perception nor inaccessible<br />

<strong>to</strong> us; it is revealed by a <strong>the</strong>ory which, starting from perceptual data, explains<br />

those data as appearances generated by <strong>the</strong> interaction between a world of<br />

imperceptible physical a<strong>to</strong>ms and sensory mechanisms also composed of a<strong>to</strong>ms.<br />

But now, as Sextus points out (ibid. VIII.56 (not in DK)) and Democritus<br />

himself recognized (in <strong>the</strong> famous ‘complaint of <strong>the</strong> senses’ (fr. 125)) scepticism<br />

threatens once again; for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory has <strong>to</strong> take perceptual data as its startingpoint,<br />

so if <strong>the</strong> senses are al<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r unreliable, <strong>the</strong>re are no reliable data on<br />

which <strong>to</strong> base <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. So, as <strong>the</strong> senses say <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind in fragment 125, ‘Our<br />

overthrow is a fall for you.’<br />

Commenta<strong>to</strong>rs who (like Barnes [2.8]) read fragment 125 as expressing<br />

commitment <strong>to</strong> scepticism (despairing or exultant, according <strong>to</strong> taste) on <strong>the</strong> part<br />

of Democritus, naturally reject <strong>the</strong> unitary interpretation proffered above. On this<br />

view fragments 117 and 6–10 are not restricted <strong>to</strong> sensory cognition, but express<br />

a full-blooded rejection of any form of knowledge, which must be seen as<br />

superseding <strong>the</strong> distinction between appearance and reality of fragments 9 (first<br />

part) and 11 and <strong>the</strong> claim <strong>to</strong> ‘genuine knowledge’ in <strong>the</strong> latter. Yet Sextus<br />

presents 6–11 in a single context (Adversus Ma<strong>the</strong>maticos VII.135–40) without<br />

any suggestion of a conflict within <strong>the</strong> collection. Moreover, in Outlines of<br />

Pyrrhonism I.213–4 (not in DK) he points out that, though <strong>the</strong> Sceptics resemble<br />

Democritus in appealing <strong>to</strong> phenomena of conflicting appearances, such as <strong>the</strong><br />

honey which tastes sweet <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> healthy and bitter <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sick, in fact Democritus<br />

uses those phenomena <strong>to</strong> support, not <strong>the</strong> sceptical position that it is impossible<br />

<strong>to</strong> tell how <strong>the</strong> honey is in fact, but <strong>the</strong> dogmatic position that <strong>the</strong> honey is itself<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r sweet nor bitter. (I interpret <strong>the</strong> latter as <strong>the</strong> assertion that sweetness and<br />

bitterness are not intrinsic attributes of <strong>the</strong> structure of a<strong>to</strong>ms which is <strong>the</strong> honey<br />

(see above).) Sextus, in short, sees Democritus not as a sceptic, but as a<br />

dogmatist. Indeed, Sextus does not cite fragment 125, and it is possible that he<br />

did not know <strong>the</strong> text from which it comes; VIII.56 shows that he was aware of<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem which is dramatized in <strong>the</strong> fragment, but he clearly saw it as a<br />

difficulty for Democritus, ra<strong>the</strong>r than as signalling Democritus’ rejection of <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of his own <strong>the</strong>ory.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!