04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

242 THE SOPHISTS<br />

Euthydemus and Dionysodorus were bro<strong>the</strong>rs and came originally from Chios.<br />

In Pla<strong>to</strong>’s Euthydemus <strong>the</strong>y are addressed as sophists (271 CI) and are said <strong>to</strong><br />

have had many pupils. Euthydemus’ most distinctive doctrine is perhaps that<br />

referred <strong>to</strong> in Pla<strong>to</strong>’s Cratylus (386d), namely that all things belong equally <strong>to</strong> all<br />

things at <strong>the</strong> same time and always. The most likely explanation of this statement<br />

is that which takes it as meaning that all things possess all attributes <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r and<br />

all <strong>the</strong> time. If this is what he is saying, <strong>the</strong>n it would seem <strong>to</strong> provide an<br />

underlying basis for Protagoras’ man-measure doctrine. All perceived qualities<br />

are in fact always present in perceived objects, and this is shown by <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

<strong>the</strong> verbal attribution of any quality <strong>to</strong> any thing is always possible. Words only<br />

have meaning because <strong>the</strong>y refer <strong>to</strong> what is actually <strong>the</strong> case. This would explain<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctrine attributed <strong>to</strong> Dionysodorus (Euthydemus 284c5) according <strong>to</strong> which<br />

no one says things that are false: all statements that anyone can make are true<br />

because all attributes are necessarily actually present in <strong>the</strong> things <strong>to</strong> which<br />

reference is being made. Consequently it is not possible <strong>to</strong> make genuinely<br />

contradic<strong>to</strong>ry statements, since contradiction would be asserting that one<br />

statement is true and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r which conflicts with it is false.<br />

Three names in addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> above may be mentioned in passing. Critias,<br />

who was a first cousin of Pla<strong>to</strong>’s mo<strong>the</strong>r, was one of <strong>the</strong> Thirty Tyrants who held<br />

power at A<strong>the</strong>ns at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> Peloponnesian war. He was classed as a<br />

sophist by Philostratus, and has regularly been listed among <strong>the</strong> sophists ever<br />

since, down <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> present day. He wrote tragedies, in at least one of which he<br />

included a rationalizing account of belief in <strong>the</strong> gods. But he is not known <strong>to</strong><br />

have been a teacher, and he should accordingly in all probability be excluded<br />

from <strong>the</strong> list of sophists. The opposite is <strong>the</strong> case with <strong>the</strong> thinker Antis<strong>the</strong>nes of<br />

A<strong>the</strong>ns who came <strong>to</strong> be regarded as <strong>the</strong> founder of <strong>the</strong> Cynic sect. As a result he<br />

has usually been discussed by modern writers under <strong>the</strong> general heading of <strong>the</strong><br />

Cynic movement. But his claims <strong>to</strong> have been <strong>the</strong> founder of this movement are<br />

subject <strong>to</strong> serious doubt, and <strong>the</strong>re is fairly convincing evidence that he should<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r be classed as a sophist. 12 He lived a long life, from <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> fifth<br />

century long in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> fourth century BC. We know from Aris<strong>to</strong>tle (Metaphysics<br />

1024b26) that he held <strong>the</strong> two distinctive sophistic doctrines that we have already<br />

mentioned several times, namely that it is not possible <strong>to</strong> contradict and that it is<br />

not possible <strong>to</strong> say what is false.<br />

The final name <strong>to</strong> be mentioned here is that of Socrates. Although presented<br />

by Pla<strong>to</strong> as <strong>the</strong> arch-enemy of <strong>the</strong> sophists and all <strong>the</strong>y s<strong>to</strong>od for, it is none <strong>the</strong><br />

less true that Socrates can only be unders<strong>to</strong>od if he is seen as a member of <strong>the</strong><br />

world in which he lived. Socrates had a great influence on <strong>the</strong> young men who<br />

became his disciples, even though he did not accept any payment from <strong>the</strong>m for<br />

his teaching. Two things at least emerge clearly from what Pla<strong>to</strong> has <strong>to</strong> tell us:<br />

Socrates had begun early in his life with a critical interest in <strong>the</strong> problems of<br />

physical science (Phaedo 96a–99d), and he also deployed a distinctive method of<br />

argument which involved <strong>the</strong> refutation of unacceptable propositions and <strong>the</strong><br />

promotion of acceptable answers <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> question ‘What is <strong>the</strong> correct account <strong>to</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!