04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

GREEK ARITHMETIC, GEOMETRY AND HARMONICS 267<br />

distance of ships at sea requires <strong>the</strong> use of this <strong>the</strong>orem. (352.14–18, all four<br />

passages in DK 11 A 20)<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r passages 24 credit Thales with a method for determining <strong>the</strong> height of a<br />

pyramid by measuring its shadow and call him ‘<strong>the</strong> first <strong>to</strong> describe <strong>the</strong> right<br />

triangle of a circle’, whatever that may mean. However, <strong>the</strong> crucial passages are<br />

<strong>the</strong> four I have quoted. Dicks ([8.88], 302–3) seizes on <strong>the</strong> last <strong>to</strong> argue that<br />

Eudemus’ attributions <strong>to</strong> Thales are reconstructions which presuppose that<br />

Thales demonstrated in a basically Euclidean way geometrical <strong>the</strong>orems implicit<br />

in his more practical accomplishments. Even if one accepts <strong>the</strong> plausibility of<br />

this approach <strong>to</strong> ancient doxographical reports, two features of <strong>the</strong>se particular<br />

ones may cause one <strong>to</strong> hesitate: <strong>the</strong> detailed point in (b) about Thales’ archaic<br />

vocabulary, and <strong>the</strong> fact that in (a) Thales is said <strong>to</strong> have proved something<br />

which is (illegitimately) made a matter of definition in Euclid’s Elements (I, def.<br />

17).<br />

It is also striking that all four of <strong>the</strong> propositions ascribed <strong>to</strong> Thales can be<br />

‘proved’ ei<strong>the</strong>r by superimposing one figure on ano<strong>the</strong>r (d) or by ‘folding’ a<br />

configuration at a point of symmetry. It seems possible that Thales’ proofs were<br />

what we might call convincing pictures involving no explicit deductive structure.<br />

But once one ascribes even this much of a conception of justification <strong>to</strong> Thales,<br />

one is faced with what would seem <strong>to</strong> be serious questions. How did it come<br />

about that Thales would formulate, say, <strong>the</strong> claim that a diameter bisects a circle?<br />

If he was just interested in <strong>the</strong> truth ‘for its own sake’, <strong>the</strong>n we already have <strong>the</strong><br />

idea of pure geometrical knowledge. But if, as seems more plausible, he was<br />

interested in <strong>the</strong> claim as a means <strong>to</strong> justifying some o<strong>the</strong>r less obvious one, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

we seem <strong>to</strong> have <strong>the</strong> concept of ma<strong>the</strong>matical deduction, from which <strong>the</strong><br />

evolution of <strong>the</strong> concept of ma<strong>the</strong>matical proof is not hard <strong>to</strong> envisage. We need<br />

not, of course, suppose that Thales was a rigorous reasoner by Euclidean<br />

standards; merely saying that he explicitly asserted and tried <strong>to</strong> justify<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matical propositions of a ra<strong>the</strong>r elementary kind is enough <strong>to</strong> give us a<br />

primitive form of ma<strong>the</strong>matics.<br />

Of course, we would like <strong>to</strong> know something about <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical background<br />

of Thales’ interests. Proclus and o<strong>the</strong>r ancient sources give credit <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Egyptians,<br />

but modern scholars tend <strong>to</strong> be sceptical about <strong>the</strong>se claims. 25 Van der Waerden<br />

and o<strong>the</strong>rs have invoked <strong>the</strong> Babylonians <strong>to</strong> fill <strong>the</strong> gap. I quote from his<br />

discussion of Thales ([8.13], 89), which shows that he also credits Thales with a<br />

high standard of ma<strong>the</strong>matical argumentation.<br />

We have <strong>to</strong> abandon <strong>the</strong> traditional belief that <strong>the</strong> oldest Greek<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>maticians discovered geometry entirely by <strong>the</strong>mselves and that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

owed hardly anything <strong>to</strong> older cultures, a belief which was tenable only as<br />

long as nothing was known about Babylonian ma<strong>the</strong>matics. This in no way<br />

diminishes <strong>the</strong> stature of Thales; on <strong>the</strong> contrary, his genius receives only<br />

now <strong>the</strong> honor that is due it, <strong>the</strong> honor of having developed a logical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!