04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 387<br />

city?’ (d4–c2)). This must be because <strong>the</strong>re are no reliable generalizations<br />

linking <strong>the</strong> concrete and <strong>the</strong> abstract; absolute laws cannot do justice <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

dissimilarities of men and situations (294a10–b6). A conception of precision<br />

(t’akribes, 284d1) can only be sketched imprecisely; expert statesmen, like all<br />

practical experts (c2), must be able <strong>to</strong> measure <strong>the</strong> greater and <strong>the</strong> lesser in<br />

relation not only <strong>to</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r but <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘mean’, that is, ‘<strong>the</strong> moderate, <strong>the</strong> fitting,<br />

<strong>the</strong> timely, <strong>the</strong> necessary, and all else that falls in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> mean between extremes’<br />

(e5–8). Aris<strong>to</strong>tle was <strong>to</strong> develop this more fully, but <strong>to</strong> very different effect: Pla<strong>to</strong><br />

aspires <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> precision of an art of measurement, while he appeals <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

perception of particular cases (Nicomachean Ethics II.9.1109b22–3). Within<br />

Pla<strong>to</strong>, we must suspect, imprecision of description, and precision as an aspiration,<br />

are made for each o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

There are still roles for rules, ei<strong>the</strong>r fixed or flexible. Even expert rulers will<br />

enact laws <strong>to</strong> guide action in <strong>the</strong>ir absence (Statesman 295a4–b2); but <strong>the</strong>se are<br />

revisable by rulers, and overridable by subjects (c8–d7). More significant is <strong>the</strong><br />

right role of laws within cities whose rulers are inexpert—that is, within all cities<br />

outside U<strong>to</strong>pia (meaning ‘nowhere’). Here flexibility is dangerous. Where <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is no knowledge, revision is likely <strong>to</strong> come of corrupt motives, whereas long<br />

experience, careful consideration and popular consent lie behind laws as <strong>the</strong>y<br />

stand (300a1–b6). When rulers know what <strong>the</strong>y are doing, consent does not<br />

matter (293c8–d2); when <strong>the</strong>y do not, it does. It is if a doc<strong>to</strong>r is expert that <strong>the</strong><br />

patient’s consent has no bearing on <strong>the</strong> desirability of <strong>the</strong> treatment (296b5–c2).<br />

However, as in medicine, political consent is at best an indication, and never a<br />

criterion, of getting things right. At least <strong>the</strong> primary goal of governing well<br />

must be <strong>to</strong> act justly oneself; but its mark is just action by <strong>the</strong> governed (c6–d4),<br />

which is a consequence and not a mode of procedure. Pla<strong>to</strong> retains a counterfactual<br />

optimism: if a perfect ruler appeared, he would be welcome (301d4, cf.<br />

Republic VI.498d6–502a2); but, as it is, no such king is produced in our cities,<br />

and <strong>the</strong> best that we can do is follow in <strong>the</strong> track of <strong>the</strong> truest polity (301d8–e4).<br />

This causes Pla<strong>to</strong> no enthusiasm. If a more practicable art, like medicine or<br />

navigation, were <strong>to</strong> proceed by rigid legislation, we should all find it absurd<br />

(298b6–299e9). Such government is an imitation of <strong>the</strong> true in a manner that<br />

makes it less a copy than a counterfeit (293e2–3, cf. 300c5–301a4): far from<br />

taking <strong>the</strong> ideal as a model, it despairs of achieving more than a simulacrum of<br />

success by means that are fit less <strong>to</strong> succeed than <strong>to</strong> avoid <strong>the</strong> worst causes of<br />

failure.<br />

The Laws deepens and develops what is essentially <strong>the</strong> same conception, but<br />

with much more patience for <strong>the</strong> unideal. Its protagonist is an A<strong>the</strong>nian Stranger,<br />

who lacks at once <strong>the</strong> uncertainties and <strong>the</strong> aspirations of a Socrates. He<br />

distinguishes a ‘first city and polity’, which realizes <strong>the</strong> greatest possible unity,<br />

from one that is single <strong>to</strong> a secondary degree (V.739b8–e4). The ideal recalls <strong>the</strong><br />

Republic, <strong>the</strong> means are communist (women, children, property held in<br />

common), <strong>the</strong> end unanimity in attitude and action; even things private by<br />

nature, eyes and ears and hands, must seem <strong>to</strong> operate in common. There is a new

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!