04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CHAPTER 6<br />

Anaxagoras and <strong>the</strong> a<strong>to</strong>mists<br />

C.C.W.Taylor<br />

ANAXAGORAS<br />

In <strong>the</strong> course of <strong>the</strong> fifth century BC <strong>the</strong> political and cultural pre-eminence of<br />

A<strong>the</strong>ns attracted <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> city a considerable number of intellectuals of various<br />

kinds from all over <strong>the</strong> Greek world. This phenomenon, <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘Sophistic<br />

Movement’, is fully described in <strong>the</strong> next chapter; here it suffices <strong>to</strong> point out that,<br />

in addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussions of moral and <strong>the</strong>ological questions for which <strong>the</strong><br />

sophists are more widely known, <strong>the</strong> activities of many of <strong>the</strong>m included<br />

popularization and extension <strong>to</strong> new areas, such as <strong>the</strong> study of <strong>the</strong> origins of<br />

civilization, of <strong>the</strong> Ionian tradition of general speculative enquiry in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

world (see Chapter 2). Anaxagoras stands out from his sophistic contemporaries<br />

as a truly original thinker, who sought not merely <strong>to</strong> transmit <strong>the</strong> Ionian tradition,<br />

but <strong>to</strong> transform it radically in a number of ways, and in so doing <strong>to</strong> enable it <strong>to</strong><br />

meet <strong>the</strong> challenge of Eleatic logic, which had threatened <strong>the</strong> coherence of <strong>the</strong><br />

cosmological enterprise.<br />

An Ionian from Clazomenae on <strong>the</strong> central coast of Asia Minor, Anaxagoras<br />

was a contemporary of Protagoras and Empedocles. Aris<strong>to</strong>tle says (Metaphysics<br />

984a11–12: DK 59 A 43) that he was older than <strong>the</strong> latter, and (probably) that<br />

his writings are later than those of Empedocles (<strong>the</strong> interpretation of <strong>the</strong> crucial<br />

sentence is disputed). It is reliably attested that he spent thirty years in A<strong>the</strong>ns<br />

and that he was closely associated with Pericles, though <strong>the</strong>re is some dispute<br />

among scholars on when <strong>the</strong> thirty years began and ended, and whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y<br />

were a single continuous period or discontinuous. Socrates in <strong>the</strong> Phaedo (97b–<br />

98c: DK 59 A 47) describes reading Anaxagoras’ book as (probably) quite a<br />

young man, but implies that he was not personally acquainted with him; some<br />

have taken this as evidence that Anaxagoras had already left A<strong>the</strong>ns for good by<br />

about <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> century, but <strong>the</strong> evidence is weak. It is clear that, in<br />

common with o<strong>the</strong>r intellectuals, his rationalistic views on matters <strong>to</strong>uching on<br />

religion (in his case, his materialistic accounts of <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> sun and o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

heavenly bodies) made him unpopular in certain circles, and <strong>the</strong>re is a tradition<br />

(questioned by Dover [6.6]) that he had <strong>to</strong> flee from A<strong>the</strong>ns (with <strong>the</strong> assistance

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!