04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

380 PLATO: ETHICS AND POLITICS<br />

some, but not all, of <strong>the</strong> courage and imagination needed <strong>to</strong> flesh out his picture<br />

of a class of rulers unlike any rulers he knew.<br />

VI<br />

Though <strong>the</strong>y can be allowed no monopoly on altruism, philosophers must be<br />

extraordinarily motivated <strong>to</strong> serve o<strong>the</strong>rs if <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>to</strong> merit <strong>the</strong> power that Pla<strong>to</strong><br />

would place in <strong>the</strong>ir hands. At <strong>the</strong> heart even of his social philosophy lies <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of Forms. Within both personal and civic relations he expects <strong>the</strong>se <strong>to</strong> be<br />

not distracting but inspiring.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus Socrates makes an extraordinary linkage between Forms and<br />

faces. Of all <strong>the</strong> Forms, Beauty offers <strong>the</strong> clearest image of itself <strong>to</strong> our sight, so<br />

that ‘it is <strong>the</strong> most apparent and <strong>the</strong> most loved’ (2250d3–e1). We <strong>the</strong>n read that<br />

<strong>the</strong> lover would offer a sacrifice <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> boy ‘as <strong>to</strong> a statue and a god’ (251a6–7),<br />

as if a boy, unlike a god, could be both. He is clearly in a state of deep<br />

confusion, and we should not be <strong>to</strong>o quick <strong>to</strong> insist that what he really sees in <strong>the</strong><br />

boy is <strong>the</strong> image and not Beauty itself. In (and not merely while) looking at him,<br />

he is ‘carried back’ <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Form (250e2–3): passionate seeing is infused by<br />

unconscious recollecting. When he turns his attention from body <strong>to</strong> soul, <strong>the</strong><br />

same confusion recurs. He now recollects not a Form but a god, i.e., at least a<br />

mode of apprehending and realizing Forms. But gazing at <strong>the</strong> boy without<br />

grasping that he is remembering a god, he naturally credits <strong>the</strong> boy with <strong>the</strong> gifts<br />

that he in fact owes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> god and transmits <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> boy; mistaking material for<br />

model, he supposes that he is imitating <strong>the</strong> boy even as he transmutes him<br />

(252e7–253b1). The confusion is salutary, for it inspires <strong>the</strong> generosity (b7–8)<br />

that does indeed make <strong>the</strong> lover godlike: it is through finding <strong>the</strong> boy ‘equal <strong>to</strong> a<br />

god’ (255a1) that he becomes himself ‘possessed by a god’ (be). Appropriately<br />

within his defence of a higher madness, Socrates is allowing that <strong>the</strong> Forms can<br />

produce a moral revolution, replacing conventionality by au<strong>the</strong>nticity (252a4–6),<br />

through metaphysical bewilderment.<br />

The same transition from inspiration by a body <strong>to</strong> displacement of interest<br />

from body <strong>to</strong> soul was already an emphatic feature of <strong>the</strong> ladder of love in <strong>the</strong><br />

Symposium. The omission <strong>the</strong>re of any mention of recollection, a <strong>the</strong>me that<br />

Pla<strong>to</strong> was developing about <strong>the</strong> same time in <strong>the</strong> Phaedo, can only be unders<strong>to</strong>od<br />

as a sacrifice for <strong>the</strong> sake of simplicity and unity of presentation. Alternately<br />

extending and raising his view, <strong>the</strong> lover shifts his interest from one body <strong>to</strong> all<br />

beautiful bodies, <strong>to</strong> one soul, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> practices and laws that mould all beautiful<br />

souls, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> branches of knowledge, and so <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> most cognizable of all<br />

beauties, <strong>the</strong> Form of Beauty itself (210a4–e1). The Form is explicitly grasped<br />

only at <strong>the</strong> end, but must be supposed <strong>to</strong> have been exercising a subliminal<br />

influence from <strong>the</strong> beginning. The lovers of sights and sounds in Republic Book<br />

V, who not only lack but are incapable of knowledge of <strong>the</strong> Form, are fixated on<br />

a plurality of beauties (476b4–c4, 479e1–2). Though <strong>the</strong>y doubtless use <strong>the</strong><br />

general term ‘beautiful’, <strong>the</strong>y are effectively nominalists and not realists about

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!