04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

312 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

appropriate circumstances <strong>to</strong> do what it does. A power for Socrates is not <strong>the</strong><br />

mere tendency <strong>to</strong> perform a certain sort of activity, but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> state of a thing<br />

that results in such activity. 62 Thus, for Socrates, <strong>the</strong> power is on<strong>to</strong>logically prior<br />

<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>the</strong> power is associated with. The activities are defined in virtue of<br />

<strong>the</strong> power that produces <strong>the</strong>m, not vice versa. 63<br />

Second, a power or capacity for Socrates is <strong>to</strong> be identified by its peculiar<br />

object. For example, in <strong>the</strong> Charmides, after indicating that since temperance is<br />

knowledge of knowledge it must be a power (dunamis), Socrates infers that it<br />

must be ‘of something’ (tinos einai), citing as examples that <strong>the</strong> greater has <strong>the</strong><br />

power (dunamin) <strong>to</strong> be of <strong>the</strong> lesser (168b5–8) and <strong>the</strong> double <strong>the</strong> power<br />

(dunamis) <strong>to</strong> be of <strong>the</strong> half. Thus, according <strong>to</strong> Socrates, if <strong>the</strong>re is a double of<br />

itself, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> double will be both double and half of itself. In general, he maintains<br />

that ‘<strong>the</strong> very thing which has its own power (dunamin) applied <strong>to</strong> itself will<br />

have <strong>to</strong> have that nature <strong>to</strong>wards which <strong>the</strong> power (dunamis) was directed’<br />

(Charmides 168c10–d3; adapted from Sprague trans.). He explains this with <strong>the</strong><br />

following examples: since hearing is of sound, hearing would have <strong>to</strong> be a sound<br />

if it were <strong>to</strong> be of itself, and since sight is of colour, sight would have <strong>to</strong> be coloured<br />

if it were of itself. While <strong>the</strong> details of <strong>the</strong>se passages may be difficult <strong>to</strong> sort<br />

out, <strong>the</strong> general idea appears clear enough. Associated with every power is an<br />

object, property, nature or being (ousian). Thus, <strong>the</strong> powers of <strong>the</strong> greater, <strong>the</strong><br />

double, hearing and sight have as <strong>the</strong>ir respective objects <strong>the</strong> lesser, <strong>the</strong> half,<br />

sound, and colour. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> power must always be of this object; if it were<br />

of a different object, it would be a different power. It is only on this assumption<br />

that Socrates can draw his conclusions that if <strong>the</strong> greater is of itself, <strong>the</strong>n it must<br />

be lesser (as well as greater), if <strong>the</strong> double is of itself, it must be half (as well as<br />

double) 64 , if hearing is of itself, it must be a sound, and if sight is of itself, it<br />

must be coloured. 65<br />

Thus, since virtue is an expertise, it is a power. As a power it must be<br />

associated with a particular sort of activity and have a specific object. The<br />

activity is evidently virtuous activity 66 , while <strong>the</strong> object appears <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> good<br />

(and <strong>the</strong> bad) in light of our earlier discussion. But in saying this we have left out<br />

<strong>the</strong> cognitive aspect of expertise. For expertise is not just a power; it is a<br />

cognitive power. This cognitive aspect of expertise is manifested in Socrates’<br />

view that expertise is infallible, inerrant or luck-independent.<br />

Consider, for example, Socrates’ claim in <strong>the</strong> first protreptic of <strong>the</strong> Euthydemus<br />

that having included wisdom in his list of goods necessary for happiness it would<br />

be superfluous <strong>to</strong> add good luck; for ‘when wisdom is present no good luck is<br />

lacking <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> one for whom it is present’ (Euthydemus 280b2–3). The idea here<br />

is that <strong>the</strong> person with wisdom or knowledge will invariably make decisions or<br />

choices conducive <strong>to</strong> his or her happiness. Just as <strong>the</strong> expert ship pilot invariably<br />

makes decisions or choices conducive <strong>to</strong> getting <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> port safely, given <strong>the</strong><br />

circumstances she is in, so <strong>the</strong> wise or knowledgeable individual will invariably<br />

make decisions or choices conducive <strong>to</strong> attaining happiness, given her<br />

circumstances. Many scholars believe that Socrates takes <strong>the</strong>se choices <strong>to</strong> be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!