04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

410 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

apparent casualness, in <strong>the</strong> whole corpus, and never appears as a character). But<br />

this in itself raises a familiar question. If poetry is such a bad thing, and he attacks<br />

it so regularly, why does he so regularly borrow (or appropriate) its methods?<br />

That he does so will be true even without <strong>the</strong> argument just derived from <strong>the</strong><br />

Symposium and <strong>the</strong> Laws, if it is an essential feature of poetry that it appeals <strong>to</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> irrational in us, 75 since <strong>the</strong> dialogues <strong>the</strong>mselves frequently combine<br />

reasoned argument with techniques which rely directly on an emotional response<br />

from <strong>the</strong> reader (s<strong>to</strong>ries, persuasive descriptions, analogies, and so on). 76 The<br />

answer is straightforward enough: Pla<strong>to</strong> uses such methods precisely because he<br />

recognizes <strong>the</strong>ir power, and because he is in business <strong>to</strong> persuade us. In any case<br />

he repeatedly suggests that poetry itself might be useful. It is only because<br />

existing poetry embraces ideals and teaches notions which are so different from<br />

his own that he must reject it (reluctantly, if he is anything like his Socrates). In<br />

particular, it portrays life in all its complexity and plurality, when—as he sees it<br />

—it should be describing <strong>the</strong> single, simple, best life. 77<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus, Pla<strong>to</strong> formulates a <strong>the</strong>ory of philosophical writing in terms of<br />

‘rhe<strong>to</strong>ric’, <strong>the</strong> art of addressing audiences through <strong>the</strong> spoken and written word.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> ideal Pla<strong>to</strong>nic world, rhe<strong>to</strong>ric <strong>to</strong>o— normally <strong>the</strong> property of politicians<br />

and o<strong>the</strong>rs allegedly more interested in style than in substance—would be<br />

reformed and become <strong>the</strong> ally ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> opponent of philosophy. 78 The<br />

ideal writer will be someone who knows about both his subject and <strong>the</strong> nature of<br />

<strong>the</strong> soul, who is able <strong>to</strong> ‘discover <strong>the</strong> form [of discourse] which fits each nature,<br />

and so arrange and order his logos [i.e. what he speaks or writes], offering a<br />

complex soul complex logoi containing all <strong>the</strong> modes, and simple logoi <strong>to</strong> a simple<br />

soul’ (Phaedrus 277b–c). The ‘simple’ soul here appears <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> one dominated<br />

by reason, while <strong>the</strong> ‘complex’ or ‘variegated’ (poikilos, ‘many-coloured’) soul<br />

for its part recalls <strong>the</strong> democratic type of individual in Republic VIII, in whom no<br />

single element or desire is in firm control; for <strong>the</strong> latter, Pla<strong>to</strong> acknowledges that<br />

a purely rational mode of address will not be sufficient, and will need <strong>to</strong> be<br />

supplemented by o<strong>the</strong>r means. Playing on <strong>the</strong> emotions of one’s audience will<br />

cause nothing but trouble in <strong>the</strong> hands of <strong>the</strong> ignorant, whe<strong>the</strong>r he is an ora<strong>to</strong>r or<br />

a poet; for <strong>the</strong> knowledgeable writer and teacher, it is an indispensable <strong>to</strong>ol if he<br />

is <strong>to</strong> address any but those already persuaded of <strong>the</strong> value of philosophy.<br />

A distinction of <strong>the</strong> sort in <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus passage, between <strong>the</strong> simple and <strong>the</strong><br />

‘many-coloured’ is central <strong>to</strong> Pla<strong>to</strong>’s thinking about literature and art in general.<br />

The simple, straightforward, and unmixed tends <strong>to</strong> be identified as good; <strong>the</strong><br />

varied, and especially what is innovative, as bad. The most extreme statement of<br />

such an idea is probably in <strong>the</strong> Philebus, where Socrates is identifying ‘true’, i.e.<br />

pure and unmixed, pleasures. These are related <strong>to</strong> beautiful colours and shapes;<br />

<strong>the</strong>y include ‘most pleasures of smell, and those of hearing’, all those cases<br />

where <strong>the</strong>re is no antecedent or concomitant pain. He <strong>the</strong>n explains what he<br />

means by a beautiful shape in this context. It is not what ‘<strong>the</strong> many’ would mean<br />

by it, pointing <strong>to</strong> a living creature or a painting, but ra<strong>the</strong>r

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!