04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

320 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

should we take) what he believes <strong>to</strong> be relevant <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> results of this particular<br />

elenchos.<br />

48 Again, I do not intend here <strong>to</strong> suggest that this is <strong>the</strong> conclusion Socrates thinks he<br />

has established by means of his elenchos with Nicias at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> Laches. See<br />

previous note.<br />

49 To see how Socrates may have taken <strong>the</strong>se two contrasts <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> same consider<br />

Socrates’ example of <strong>the</strong> miner who produces gold. This expert can produce gold<br />

successfully lacking knowledge of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad. But he can’t produce it<br />

beneficially—that is, produce it in a way that will benefit him—if he lacks <strong>the</strong><br />

knowledge of how <strong>to</strong> use it, that is, if he lacks <strong>the</strong> knowledge of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong><br />

bad. If we are <strong>to</strong> take <strong>the</strong>se two contrasts <strong>to</strong> be essentially <strong>the</strong> same and we are <strong>to</strong><br />

take <strong>the</strong> knowledge or expertise of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad as <strong>the</strong> knowledge or<br />

expertise that makes us happy and fare well—that is, virtue—<strong>the</strong>n what is <strong>the</strong><br />

product of this knowledge? The good. In taking virtue <strong>to</strong> be an expertise we may or<br />

may not need <strong>to</strong> view it as essentially productive. For important discussions<br />

surrounding this issue see Irwin [9.34] and Roochnik [9.76].<br />

50 Again, however, I hasten <strong>to</strong> point out that I do not take this <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> ‘hidden<br />

meaning’ of <strong>the</strong> Charmides or <strong>the</strong> conclusion Socrates takes his elenchoi in <strong>the</strong><br />

Charmides <strong>to</strong> establish. See previous notes on <strong>the</strong> Laches.<br />

51 Brickhouse and Smith [9.17], 6–7. Note that <strong>the</strong>y prefer <strong>to</strong> translate technē as<br />

‘craft’ ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘expertise’. See also Reeve [9.73], 37–53, Woodruff [9.96], 68–<br />

81, and Irwin [9.34], 73–7.<br />

52 See Brickhouse and Smith [9.17], 37, Penner [9.69], 197, Penner [9.68], 321–2,<br />

Ferejohn [9.24], 383 n. 18, Ferejohn [9.23], 15 and Irwin [9.34], 296 n. 28.<br />

53 See also Republic 346a1–3 and Charmides 168b2–4.<br />

54 Taylor [9.82], 84 glosses this as perhaps spinning, weaving, pottery and cultivation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> olive.<br />

55 See Protagoras 320e2–3.<br />

56 See also Protagoras 331d1–e4, 333a1–b6, 349b1–c5, and<br />

57 I owe <strong>the</strong> clear expression of this objection <strong>to</strong> C.C.W.Taylor.<br />

58 On Socrates’ position as contrasted with Protagoras’ here see <strong>the</strong> debate concerning<br />

<strong>the</strong> Socratic doctrine of <strong>the</strong> unity of virtues: Vlas<strong>to</strong>s [9.87], 221–70 and 418–23,<br />

Penner [9.67] and [9.71], Taylor [7.22], Irwin [9.39], 31–52 and 78–94, Devereux<br />

[9.20] and [9.21], Ferejohn [9.23] and [9.24], and Brickhouse and Smith [9–17].<br />

60–72 and 103–36.<br />

59 Hippias Minor 365d6–366a4, Gorgias 509d2–e1, and Hippias Major 296a4–6. See<br />

also <strong>the</strong> Prome<strong>the</strong>us s<strong>to</strong>ry mentioned above in which Protagoras sometimes has<br />

Epime<strong>the</strong>us doling out <strong>the</strong> powers, for example strength and speed, and sometimes<br />

<strong>the</strong> things in virtue of which <strong>the</strong> creature has a particular power, for example thick<br />

hair.<br />

60 See, for example, Republic 477d7–61 where Pla<strong>to</strong>—as opposed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Socrates of<br />

<strong>the</strong> early dialogues—explicitly identifies knowledge (epistēmē) and belief (doxa) as<br />

powers or capacities.<br />

61 I say ‘typically’ because it is difficult <strong>to</strong> say what activities are associated with <strong>the</strong><br />

powers of <strong>the</strong> greater, <strong>the</strong> double, <strong>the</strong> heavier, <strong>the</strong> lighter, <strong>the</strong> older, and <strong>the</strong><br />

younger in <strong>the</strong> Charmides (168b-d), for example.<br />

62 See Irwin’s A-powers (‘x and y have <strong>the</strong> same A-power when each of <strong>the</strong>m does F<br />

(where F is some kind of behaviour); each of <strong>the</strong>m has <strong>the</strong> power <strong>to</strong> F’) versus B-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!