04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

308 FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO<br />

Consider first <strong>the</strong> Laches. When Laches proposes wise endurance as <strong>the</strong><br />

proper definition of courage (192d10–12), Socrates enquires whe<strong>the</strong>r he thinks<br />

that those who endure <strong>the</strong> relevant dangers with <strong>the</strong> expertise of horsemen, or <strong>the</strong><br />

expertise of <strong>the</strong> sling, or <strong>the</strong> expertise of <strong>the</strong> bow, or <strong>the</strong> expertise of well-divers,<br />

or any o<strong>the</strong>r expertise of this sort are more or less courageous than those who<br />

endure without <strong>the</strong> relevant expertise (193b9–c8). Laches answers that <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

less courageous, and so abandons his definition. The suggestion is that whatever<br />

<strong>the</strong> proper definition of courage may be, it appears not <strong>to</strong> be wise endurance<br />

when wisdom is unders<strong>to</strong>od as <strong>the</strong>se sorts of expertise. 47 Moreover, when<br />

Socrates turns <strong>to</strong> Nicias’ definition that courage is knowledge of fearful and<br />

daring things, he asks Nicias whe<strong>the</strong>r knowledge of fearful and daring things is<br />

anything o<strong>the</strong>r than knowledge of future goods and evils. Nicias responds that it<br />

is not. Next, Socrates asks whe<strong>the</strong>r it belongs <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> same knowledge <strong>to</strong> know<br />

future, past and present things. When Nicias answers that it does, Socrates points<br />

out that it follows on Nicias’ view that courage is knowledge of all goods and<br />

evils, which is <strong>the</strong> whole of virtue and not its part, contrary <strong>to</strong> Nicias’ initial<br />

claim that courage is part of virtue. Again, whatever we take Socrates’ view <strong>to</strong> be<br />

concerning <strong>the</strong> proper definition of courage, <strong>the</strong> suggestion here seems <strong>to</strong> be that<br />

in so far as courage is defined as knowledge of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad it will be<br />

identical <strong>to</strong> virtue, not a part of it. 48 Virtue, according <strong>to</strong> Socrates in <strong>the</strong> Laches,<br />

appears <strong>to</strong> be knowledge of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad. Here, <strong>the</strong>n, we have a hint of<br />

Socrates’ answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> question with which we were left at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> second<br />

protreptic of <strong>the</strong> Euthydemus. The knowledge or expertise that is virtue—that is<br />

necessary <strong>to</strong> make us happy and fare well—is not a knowledge or expertise like<br />

horsemanship or well-diving, but <strong>the</strong> knowledge or expertise of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong><br />

bad.<br />

Finally, we can turn <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Charmides. The last half of this dialogue consists<br />

of a long, complicated, and often <strong>to</strong>rtuous discussion of Critias’ definition that<br />

temperance is knowledge of oneself (164d3–5). By 173a this definition has been<br />

modified <strong>to</strong> mean that temperance is knowledge of what one knows and does not<br />

know (172c9), and as Socrates conceded earlier, life in accordance with that<br />

knowledge would be free from error (171d6–172a3). Now Socrates relates a<br />

dream in which temperance—unders<strong>to</strong>od as knowledge of what one knows and<br />

does not know—rules (archoi he sōphrosunē). He grants that in such a situation<br />

one would live according <strong>to</strong> knowledge and so be free from error, but he<br />

wonders whe<strong>the</strong>r one would fare well and be happy (eu an prat<strong>to</strong>imen kai<br />

eudaimonoimen). Ultimately, Socrates and Critias agree that one would not. After<br />

denying that it is <strong>the</strong> knowledge of draught-playing (petteutikon), calculation<br />

(logistikon), or health— presumably medicine—that makes one fare well or be<br />

happy, Critias asserts that it is knowledge of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad (174b10). This<br />

leads Socrates <strong>to</strong> ask whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> doc<strong>to</strong>r is any less successful in producing<br />

health or <strong>the</strong> shoemaker is any less successful at making shoes when knowledge<br />

of <strong>the</strong> good and <strong>the</strong> bad is lacking. Critias responds that <strong>the</strong>y are not and Socrates<br />

concludes that it is <strong>the</strong> production of <strong>the</strong>se things ‘well and beneficially’ that is

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!