04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 129<br />

<strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r) nor in any respect less: all is full of what is. Hence it is all<br />

coherent, for what is comes close <strong>to</strong> what is.<br />

(DK 28 B 8.22–5)<br />

The underlying strategy here is parallel <strong>to</strong> that of section (a). Suppose that reality<br />

(E) is divided. What that implies is that something divides E. What could that<br />

be?<br />

By <strong>the</strong> fact that E is ‘summed’, comprising all that is, anything o<strong>the</strong>r than E has<br />

<strong>to</strong> be something that is not. By <strong>the</strong> same argument as before, it can never be true<br />

<strong>to</strong> say that E is divided by something that is not. Hence E is not divided by<br />

anything o<strong>the</strong>r than itself. This limb of <strong>the</strong> argument, though suppressed here as<br />

obvious, appears in <strong>the</strong> parallel passage at 8.44–8.<br />

What is here explored is <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r possibility: that E is divided by itself, i.e. by<br />

its own internal variations. The possibility of internal qualitative variations is not<br />

mentioned; presumably <strong>the</strong>y would not count as creating divisions. What is<br />

mentioned is <strong>the</strong> possibility of variations of ‘more’ and ‘less’, i.e. in ‘quantity’ or<br />

‘intensity’ of being. These are rejected, by <strong>the</strong> observation that ‘it is all in like<br />

manner’. Being admits of no degrees; anything ei<strong>the</strong>r is or is not.<br />

(c)<br />

Reality is complete, unique, unchanging (B 8.26–33)<br />

The same, staying in <strong>the</strong> same, by itself it lies, and thus it stays fixed<br />

<strong>the</strong>re; for strong necessity holds it in <strong>the</strong> fetters of <strong>the</strong> limit, which<br />

fences it about; since it is not right that what is should be incomplete,<br />

for it is not lacking—if it were, it would lack everything.<br />

(DK 28 B 8.29–33)<br />

This is a train of argument in which exposition runs <strong>the</strong> opposite way <strong>to</strong><br />

deduction. It must be read backwards from <strong>the</strong> end. The starting-point is that<br />

reality (E) is complete or ‘not lacking’. Once again <strong>the</strong> strategy is <strong>the</strong> same, that<br />

of reductio ad absurdum. Suppose E is lacking; <strong>the</strong>n E must lack something.<br />

What is this something? It cannot be part of E, for <strong>the</strong>n it would not be lacking<br />

from E. Therefore it is not part of E, and hence is not; but it is not true that it is<br />

not, by <strong>the</strong> now familiar argument.<br />

Given that E is not lacking, it is complete, and has a ‘limit’. The word used here<br />

has no close English equivalent: Homer’s usage applies it <strong>to</strong> anything that marks<br />

or achieves any kind of completion. Here, <strong>the</strong> ‘limit’ functions as a constraint on<br />

reality: <strong>the</strong> need for completeness is a (logical) constraint. Completeness rules out,<br />

in particular, all change and movement, and enforces uniqueness: reality is ‘by<br />

itself’ or ‘on its own’. Why?<br />

Completeness has <strong>the</strong>se consequences because it embodies <strong>the</strong> principle that E<br />

contains everything that is. This now enables Parmenides <strong>to</strong> get some grip on <strong>the</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!