04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 147<br />

development of ma<strong>the</strong>matics as an abstract study. 51 This <strong>the</strong>ory is propounded, it<br />

seems, on <strong>the</strong> basis of an analysis of ordinary human knowledge and its<br />

presuppositions.<br />

Philolaus’ starting-point is gnōsis, <strong>the</strong> everyday activity of cognitive<br />

‘grasping’ (individuation, identification, reidentification, reference) of ordinary<br />

individual things. This ‘cognizing’ implies that its objects ‘have number’, i.e. are<br />

in some sense measurable or countable. Quite generally, any cognizable object<br />

must be marked off from everything else by a sharp, definite boundary. Whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

this boundary be spatial or temporal, <strong>the</strong> object within it will have some<br />

measurable quantity (volume, time-duration). Also, a cognizable collection of<br />

objects must have a number; indeed even a single object must be recognizable as<br />

a single object and not a plurality, which implies a definite and practically<br />

applicable method of counting. These points are recognizably related <strong>to</strong> some<br />

arguments of Parmenides and Zeno. Zeno (see above, pp. 153–4) argues that a<br />

‘many’ implies a definite number; but also that it implies definite, distinct units<br />

and hence boundaries round <strong>the</strong>se units. That what is must be a unit and have a<br />

boundary is also argued in Parmenides (see above, p. 41).<br />

The concept of a ‘boundary’ is central here. Philolaus’ analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

presuppositions of cognition leads him <strong>to</strong> a logical separation of <strong>the</strong> contents of<br />

<strong>the</strong> universe in<strong>to</strong> ‘things which bound’ and ‘things unbounded’. Everything in<br />

<strong>the</strong> cosmos, and that cosmos itself, is claimed manifestly <strong>to</strong> exhibit a structure<br />

‘fitted <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r’ from <strong>the</strong> two kinds of thing. This dualism is obviously closely<br />

related <strong>to</strong> views which Aris<strong>to</strong>tle attributes <strong>to</strong> ‘<strong>the</strong> people called Pythagoreans’.<br />

He reports that some of <strong>the</strong>m set up two ‘columns of correlated opposites’, which<br />

featured such items as limit/unlimited, odd/even, one/plurality, right/ left, male/<br />

female, etc. (Metaphysics I. 5, 986a22–6).<br />

Philolaus’ careful attempt <strong>to</strong> build up a general on<strong>to</strong>logy on <strong>the</strong> basis of an<br />

analysis of ordinary cognition, guided by ma<strong>the</strong>matics, leads him naturally in <strong>the</strong><br />

direction of Aris<strong>to</strong>telian ‘form’ and ‘matter’. Whatever stuff an individual is<br />

thought of as being ‘made of, is in itself not ‘bounded’; for it might be present in<br />

any quantity. But for <strong>the</strong>re <strong>to</strong> be an individual, <strong>the</strong>re must be also a ‘bound’.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r explication of just what is involved in this ‘fitting <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r’ is not<br />

found, and it seems that Philolaus thought this question beyond <strong>the</strong> reach of<br />

human knowledge. That conclusion is in conformity with his method. The<br />

‘everlasting being’ of things, or ‘nature itself, is <strong>the</strong> subject of ‘divine cognition’<br />

only. The ‘fitting <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r’ is achieved ‘in some way or o<strong>the</strong>r’. Ma<strong>the</strong>matics,<br />

clearly, cannot help; for it <strong>to</strong>o exemplifies, ra<strong>the</strong>r than explains, <strong>the</strong> dualistic<br />

structure. All that we can say is that even humble human cognition presupposes<br />

such a structure of things in particular and in general; <strong>the</strong> first example, it has<br />

been suggested, of a Kantian transcendental argument. 52

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!