04.01.2013 Views

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

From the Beginning to Plato

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

FROM THE BEGINNING TO PLATO 151<br />

4 The fragments of Parmenides have been edited many times. DK is <strong>the</strong> standard<br />

edition for reference purposes; <strong>the</strong> most reliable and informed recent edition, on<br />

matters of Greek linguistic usage and of textual his<strong>to</strong>ry, is that of Coxon [4.8],<br />

which also gives much <strong>the</strong> fullest collection of secondary ancient evidence. Among<br />

minor sources are some o<strong>the</strong>r Neopla<strong>to</strong>nists (Plotinus, Iamblichus, Proclus), and<br />

Sextus Empiricus <strong>the</strong> Sceptic.<br />

5 The scholarly literature is extensive. A small selection is given in <strong>the</strong> bibliography;<br />

<strong>the</strong> monograph of Mourela<strong>to</strong>s [4.24] can be particularly recommended for clarity,<br />

fullness of information and breadth of approach. The footnotes below offer very<br />

brief indications of <strong>the</strong> spread of opinion on cardinal points; <strong>the</strong>y do not try <strong>to</strong><br />

outline <strong>the</strong> arguments needed <strong>to</strong> justify <strong>the</strong> reading given in <strong>the</strong> text.<br />

6 On Xenophanes and his relevance here, Hussey [2.35], 17–32.<br />

7 On <strong>the</strong> ‘opinions of mortals’ see below pp. 147–9.<br />

8 On alē<strong>the</strong>iē and related words in early Greek, scholarly discussion has been <strong>to</strong>o<br />

often darkened by philosophical prejudice. See <strong>the</strong> useful study of Heitsch [4.29];<br />

also Mourela<strong>to</strong>s [4.24], 63–7 and references <strong>the</strong>re.<br />

Alē<strong>the</strong>iē in Parmenides is taken as ‘reality’ by Verdenius [4.30], Mourela<strong>to</strong>s [4.<br />

24], 63–7, Coxon [4.8], 168. O<strong>the</strong>rs understand it as ‘truth’ or ‘manifest or<br />

necessary truth’.<br />

9 So Verdenius [4.30]. Allied <strong>to</strong> this view are those who take <strong>the</strong> intended subject <strong>to</strong><br />

be ‘what is’ in <strong>the</strong> sense of ‘what is <strong>the</strong> case’ (e.g. Mourela<strong>to</strong>s [4.24]). O<strong>the</strong>r<br />

leading candidates for <strong>the</strong> role of subject of discourse: ‘that which is’ (so e.g.<br />

Cornford [4.19], Verdenius [4.27], Hölscher [4.22], O’Brien [4.12]); ‘what can be<br />

spoken and thought of (Owen [4.46]), ‘whatever may be <strong>the</strong> object of enquiry’<br />

(Barnes [2.8]). That a wholly indefinite subject (‘something’) or no specific subject<br />

at all is intended, at least initially, is suggested in different ways by e.g. Calogero<br />

[4.18], Coxon [4.8].<br />

10 On <strong>the</strong> verb einai ‘be’ in early Greek, see items [4.31] <strong>to</strong> [4.34] in <strong>the</strong> Bibliography.<br />

The entirely straightforward Homeric usage (‘X is’—‘<strong>the</strong>re is such a thing as X’) is<br />

<strong>the</strong> obvious first hypo<strong>the</strong>sis for <strong>the</strong> esti and ouk esti paths. Some, though, have put<br />

<strong>the</strong> so-called ‘veridical’ uses (‘be’=‘be true’ or ‘be’=‘be so’, ‘be <strong>the</strong> case’) in <strong>the</strong><br />

forefront (e.g. Jantzen [4.23], Kahn [4.42]); o<strong>the</strong>rs make <strong>the</strong> use of einai in<br />

predication central (e.g. Mourela<strong>to</strong>s [4.24]); yet o<strong>the</strong>rs (Calogero [4.18], Furth [4.<br />

41]) have suggested that in Parmenides this verb is a ‘fusion’ of two or more of <strong>the</strong><br />

normal uses.<br />

11 In fact premiss (2), even without (1) and (3), gives a reason <strong>to</strong> reject <strong>the</strong> way that<br />

says ‘it is not’. For this way says, about reality generally, that it doesn’t exist or<br />

obtain. So by its own account it can’t state any truth, since truth presupposes reality.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>re is nothing <strong>to</strong> show that Parmenides <strong>to</strong>ok this short cut.<br />

12 Pla<strong>to</strong> Theaetetus 188c9–189b6, Sophist 237b7-e7. On <strong>the</strong> versions of this argument<br />

in Pla<strong>to</strong>, see e.g. items [4.49] <strong>to</strong> [4.51] in <strong>the</strong> Bibliography.<br />

13 It is true that in places <strong>the</strong> words ‘say’ (legein, phasthai), ‘think’ (noein) and <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

derivatives are used in ways that seem inconsistent with principle (7). (a) The<br />

goddess describes (at least) two ways as those ‘which alone are <strong>to</strong> be thought’ (B 2.<br />

2), including (at least) one false one. (b) She warns Parmenides against a false way:<br />

‘fence off your thought from this way of enquiry’ (B 7.2), as though it were<br />

possible <strong>to</strong> think its falsities, (c) She speaks of ‘[my] trusty account (“saying”) and<br />

thought about reality’ (B 8.50–1), as though it were possible <strong>to</strong> have un-trusty

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!