26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Chapter 1<br />

work about presupposition, which has focused on the similarities between triggered<br />

presuppositions rather than their potential differences.<br />

I will argue that the corpus data shows that abstract presuppositions seem to<br />

be used and perceived by discourse participants <strong>in</strong> a manner similar to discourse<br />

anaphora. I will present cases where the use of presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation shares<br />

many of the characteristics identified as typical of discourse anaphora. Even <strong>in</strong><br />

cases where a resolution by b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g or a resolution by accommodation would not<br />

make a perceivable truth-conditional difference, discourse participants do seem to<br />

perceive bound presuppositions similarly to anaphoric expressions.<br />

Additionally, bound abstract presuppositions have a discourse function <strong>in</strong><br />

addition to their semantic function when they occur naturally produced <strong>in</strong> context.<br />

In cases where the presuppositional expression could have been replaced with a<br />

pronom<strong>in</strong>al anaphor, and where the semantic contribution would have been the<br />

same, I ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that an abstract presuppositional expression can have additional<br />

communicative utility, either by more precisely referr<strong>in</strong>g to an abstract idea present<br />

<strong>in</strong> the earlier context, or by contribut<strong>in</strong>g rhetorical effect by emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g a feel<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of parallelism or contrast. Presuppositional expressions can also help to summarize<br />

more precisely <strong>in</strong>formation referred to <strong>in</strong> the discourse and help make implicit<br />

conclusions explicit. These are all functions that pronom<strong>in</strong>al anaphor cannot serve<br />

or do not serve as well.<br />

The corpus results do not yield evidence that a hierarchical discourse<br />

structure constra<strong>in</strong>s the search for antecedents for presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation as has<br />

been suggested for anaphoric expressions. Presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation seems to be<br />

able to be used <strong>in</strong> a freer manner, perhaps because of its greater descriptive<br />

content.<br />

The b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g theory considers presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation to differ from empty<br />

anaphoric <strong>in</strong>formation such as pronom<strong>in</strong>al anaphors <strong>in</strong> one important respect: a<br />

presuppositional expression can create its own antecedent if the discourse does not<br />

provide one via the process of accommodation. The status of accommodated<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation, when it is used, why it is used, what licenses it, and preferences for its<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, is not clear. Most work on accommodation is highly theoretical. Our<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g of accommodation therefore would benefit from look<strong>in</strong>g at naturally<br />

produced examples and here I hope to make a contribution.<br />

There is a general misconception that presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation will be<br />

shared <strong>in</strong>formation. However, <strong>in</strong> the corpus, the majority of the presuppositions<br />

triggered by factive verbs that needed to be accommodated were believed by the<br />

speaker to be new to the hearer. Often the po<strong>in</strong>t of the utterance was the<br />

presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation. This confirms earlier empirical observations that other<br />

presupposition triggers, <strong>in</strong> particular it-clefts (Pr<strong>in</strong>ce 1978, Del<strong>in</strong> 1995) and def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

descriptions (Fraurud 1990, Poesio & Vieira 1998) can <strong>in</strong>tentionally contribute<br />

hearer-new <strong>in</strong>formation.<br />

We still know little about what factors make it possible to understand<br />

accommodated <strong>in</strong>formation, and what affects the speaker’s choice of an expression<br />

that must be accommodated. I will argue that neither of the two explanations for<br />

2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!