26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Chapter 2<br />

(28) There is a k<strong>in</strong>g of France and the k<strong>in</strong>g of France is bald.<br />

(29) There is a k<strong>in</strong>g of France. The k<strong>in</strong>g of France is bald.<br />

Stalnaker’s analysis lets sentences jo<strong>in</strong>ed by conjunction to be semantically<br />

symmetrical, but pragmatically asymmetrical <strong>in</strong> the way the <strong>in</strong>formation contributed<br />

by speakers is understood, keep<strong>in</strong>g standard semantic def<strong>in</strong>itions of logical<br />

connectives but chang<strong>in</strong>g their effect with regard to presupposition by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

them from the perspective of the speaker’s <strong>in</strong>tended contribution. One of the nice<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs about his analysis is that many of the predictions about presupposition<br />

projection that are stipulated without a clear motivation <strong>in</strong> Karttunen (1973) and<br />

others become natural consequences of deal<strong>in</strong>g with presuppositions as<br />

assumptions made by the speaker.<br />

Karttunen (1974) offered a solution to the projection problem which is close<br />

to the ideas present <strong>in</strong> Stalnaker (1973, 1974). Rather than ask<strong>in</strong>g what<br />

presuppositions of a sentence will be projected to be part of the context, he asked<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead what the context would have to be like to satisfy or admit the sentence with<br />

its presuppositions. Contexts should be appropriate for the presuppositions of the<br />

utterances that speakers use, and he def<strong>in</strong>ed admittance conditions on contexts for<br />

complex sentences with presuppositions jo<strong>in</strong>ed by different logical connectives. He<br />

associates with each sub-clause of a sentence a so-called local context. The local<br />

context is the context plus the contribution of the earlier analyzed clauses. For<br />

example, the local context of the consequent of a conditional is the ma<strong>in</strong> context,<br />

i.e the context where it is used, plus the <strong>in</strong>formation contributed by the antecedent<br />

of the conditional. The local context of the second part of two simples sentence<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>ed by conjunction is the ma<strong>in</strong> context, plus the <strong>in</strong>formation contributed by the<br />

first conjunct. The local context should satisfy the presuppositions of the clause<br />

with the presupposition trigger<strong>in</strong>g expression, that is, elementary presuppositions<br />

should be admitted by the local context <strong>in</strong> which they are used. Sentences with<br />

presuppositions are thus <strong>in</strong>terpreted us<strong>in</strong>g a recursive contextual update<br />

mechanism that calculates what the context must be like for update to occur. For<br />

example, when <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g the presuppositions of two simple sentences jo<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

conjunction, the sentence can only update the context if two th<strong>in</strong>gs are true. The<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al context, which is the local context for the first conjunct, has to admit the<br />

presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> the first conjunct by entail<strong>in</strong>g its presuppositions.<br />

Additionally, the context that admitted the first conjunct together with the first<br />

conjunct makes up the local context for the second conjunct and also has to admit<br />

the latter by entail<strong>in</strong>g is presupposition. Otherwise the context does not admit the<br />

sentence as a whole. For example, <strong>in</strong> (27), if we beg<strong>in</strong> with an empty context c, this<br />

context must admit the presupposition of the first conjunct of this sentence. In this<br />

case there isn’t one and the context can simply be updated with the asserted<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation. The updated context must then admit the second conjunct by<br />

entail<strong>in</strong>g its presupposition, which it does, i.e. there is a k<strong>in</strong>g of France already<br />

given <strong>in</strong> the context, and this context can then be successfully updated with the<br />

16

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!