26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Chapter 4<br />

directions, it is necessary to more frequently use a full presuppositional expression<br />

rather than an anaphoric expression for clarity. The presupposition is able to<br />

summarize or jo<strong>in</strong> together this scattered <strong>in</strong>formation. That bound presuppositions<br />

can have these k<strong>in</strong>d of functions is not surpris<strong>in</strong>g, because their anaphoric<br />

alternatives, abstract object anaphoric reference, can have them as well. But the<br />

bound presuppositions can do it better, <strong>in</strong> more situations, because they have a<br />

greater descriptive content which allows them to <strong>in</strong> a more precise or ref<strong>in</strong>ed way<br />

identify exactly what previously given <strong>in</strong>formation is <strong>in</strong>tended.<br />

Another communicative function some of the examples of presuppositional<br />

b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g seems to show is stat<strong>in</strong>g some k<strong>in</strong>d of conclusion that is deducible or<br />

<strong>in</strong>ferable from the discourse record. The presupposed proposition, because parts<br />

of it have already been <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> the discourse may possibly be hearer-known if<br />

the hearer has been attentive and has made the correct conclusions. This is not<br />

always certa<strong>in</strong> however and the presupposition <strong>in</strong>creases redundancy.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g example illustrates a case where the full presuppositional<br />

expression <strong>in</strong>creases clarity. The abstract object referred to is only <strong>in</strong>ferable and not<br />

fully expressed. Speaker B is tell<strong>in</strong>g a story to Speaker a. Speaker C also knows the<br />

story. Speaker B knows that the <strong>in</strong>formation communicated is new to Speaker a,<br />

but is unsure if the <strong>in</strong>formation presupposed will be hearer-new or not. This is<br />

because it is <strong>in</strong>ferable from the earlier context (if you are put on probation you<br />

must have been prosecuted <strong>in</strong> court), but the whole focus of this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> the story<br />

is that this conclusion was not understood by Fan, a friend of the speakers. Speaker<br />

B’s addition, where she aga<strong>in</strong> makes the premiss-conclusion connection more clear<br />

by repeat<strong>in</strong>g it. This further confirms that the speakers seem to be unsure if<br />

Speaker C will be able to make the same conclusion that Fan was not able to make.<br />

(16) factive, triggered p: “she must also have been up before the court” (1-13 681)<br />

Speaker a *( - laughs)*~|<br />

Speaker B *And he was* , put <strong>in</strong> gaol. I said to Fan, well I don‘t like to rub it <strong>in</strong>, but<br />

- it must have been some {huge} affair, because - what {Fan didn‘t}<br />

realize, not be<strong>in</strong>g a lawyer, or a lawyer‘s wife - that apparently the wife<br />

was put on probation. So that Fan [?] Fan didn‘t realize that that she<br />

must also have been up {before the court}, you can‘t be put on<br />

probation, *.<br />

Speaker C *Oh yes, she was* prosecuted too, +( . coughs) ,<br />

Speaker B + burnt the books+, when she *knew that*…<br />

Speaker a *For help<strong>in</strong>g* to fiddle the <strong>in</strong>come tax~|<br />

Speaker B ( . coughs) *Well, she must have known about it.<br />

Multi-speaker dialogue may need to use presuppositions this way because<br />

establish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation as mutually known is a more complex task when several<br />

discourse participants are <strong>in</strong>volved than when only two participants are <strong>in</strong>volved.<br />

All conclusions may or may not have been realized by all discourse participants. In<br />

fact, it would be strange if we would not need to explicitly conclude th<strong>in</strong>gs on<br />

occasion, as a form of ground<strong>in</strong>g. Let’s look at a similar example of another bound<br />

propositional presupposition, the presupposition <strong>in</strong>duced by the it-cleft below.<br />

80

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!