26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Accommodation and Presupposition<br />

didn’t used to do someth<strong>in</strong>g, someone is still do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g. They are not used<br />

to <strong>in</strong>troduce new topical <strong>in</strong>formation. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example illustrates that these<br />

presuppositions are background <strong>in</strong>formation, not focus.<br />

(50) aspectual verb, triggered p: He (cous<strong>in</strong> of Speaker B) was writ<strong>in</strong>g his thesis<br />

earlier (MAINACC) (2-10 991)<br />

Speaker B: I have a cous<strong>in</strong> a bit like you actually. he used to throw his children<br />

bananas to eat . when they were hungry yes (a)<br />

Speaker c: *[gjum] ( - - - laughs)* (b)<br />

Speaker B: Just casually toss a banana, to a three month old child - tossed<br />

across the room, carry on writ<strong>in</strong>g his thesis (laughs). It was an<br />

absolute pigsty. (c)<br />

There is an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g contrast between example as (49) and (50). In example (49),<br />

the presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation is central, it is what is be<strong>in</strong>g communicated, the topic<br />

of the conversation. In example (50) the presupposition and even the asserted<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation is peripheral to the ma<strong>in</strong> story, toss<strong>in</strong>g bananas. Even if we had known<br />

that the cous<strong>in</strong> was for example a graduate student, we would still need to globally<br />

accommodate the background <strong>in</strong>formation for this specific story. I th<strong>in</strong>k this is<br />

show<strong>in</strong>g us someth<strong>in</strong>g about the difference <strong>in</strong> function between the two triggers.<br />

Accommodated aspectual verbs are general <strong>in</strong>formation that is backgrounded to<br />

the ma<strong>in</strong> topic, but accommodated factives are generally foreground <strong>in</strong>formation.<br />

Consider also the impossibility of aspectual verbs be<strong>in</strong>g used to communicate<br />

op<strong>in</strong>ions.<br />

It is difficult to see how we could ever phonetically focus the presupposition<br />

of aspectual verbs because the actual presupposition is calculated from the<br />

trigger<strong>in</strong>g expression and none of it is a surface structure that is copied or moved<br />

like with factives. Prosodic prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> the form of what is often termed pitch<br />

accent is generally considered <strong>in</strong> English to be a way to signal that <strong>in</strong>formation is<br />

focused, and when added to decontextualized examples generally suggests that the<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation associated with it is new, important, or foregrounded. The effect of<br />

phonetic focus on the surface form of the trigger can only carry over to the<br />

<strong>in</strong>duced presupposition if the presupposition is derived from some part of the<br />

surface form. But because there is no part of the surface form of aspectual<br />

presuppositions is repeated <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>duced presupposition, phonetic focus has no<br />

effect. The same is true of lexical presuppositions.<br />

For it-clefts I th<strong>in</strong>k their function plays more of a role <strong>in</strong> their tendency to<br />

occur under embedd<strong>in</strong>g and to be resolved via global accommodation. The form of<br />

it-clefts supports a correction function. This function also <strong>in</strong>fluences the way<br />

presuppositions <strong>in</strong>duced by it-clefts contribute to the discourse. <strong>Presuppositions</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>duced by it-clefts were bound a third of the time, a much higher frequency than<br />

the other abstract presuppositional triggers. When the presupposed material was<br />

bound, the antecedent was usually <strong>in</strong> the proceed<strong>in</strong>g utterance. This high frequency<br />

of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g seems to be related to this correction function. In the bound cases,<br />

147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!