26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Chapter 6<br />

The b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g theory does not really have an approach to bridg<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong> its<br />

standard form (e.g. van der Sandt 1992) will treat bridg<strong>in</strong>g anaphors by<br />

accommodation. Other ways to analyze bridg<strong>in</strong>g examples <strong>in</strong> the b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g theory are<br />

most coherently discussed <strong>in</strong> Geurts (1999). He is quite ambivalent about the need<br />

to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether bridg<strong>in</strong>g should fall under the category of b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

accommodation, po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that for many examples, both process<strong>in</strong>g strategies<br />

seem to be possible. Either a referent given <strong>in</strong> the discourse can act as an anchor,<br />

and license the creation of a new reference marker to which the presupposed<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation can be bound, or the def<strong>in</strong>ite description can be accommodated, and<br />

after accommodation this <strong>in</strong>formation can be related to the rest of the discourse<br />

record. Relat<strong>in</strong>g accommodated <strong>in</strong>formation to the discourse record is often part of<br />

the ‘wish list’ of what should be <strong>in</strong> an adequate representation of accommodation,<br />

but has yet to be developed. Geurts also po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that<br />

results from b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g the bridg<strong>in</strong>g NP, or the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that results from<br />

accommodat<strong>in</strong>g the bridg<strong>in</strong>g NP, will often be the same. This makes it difficult to<br />

say that one resolution strategy is preferred to the other.<br />

Identification of the anchor of a bridg<strong>in</strong>g NP does become essential <strong>in</strong> cases<br />

where the anchor occurs <strong>in</strong> an embedded context. Failure to recognize the<br />

connection leads to global accommodation, which sometimes results <strong>in</strong> an<br />

<strong>in</strong>correct <strong>in</strong>terpretation. For example,<br />

(5) If Drew buys a new car, he’ll ru<strong>in</strong> the brakes with<strong>in</strong> a year with his crazy<br />

driv<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

If the presupposition associated with the brakes is accommodated it will become<br />

part of the global context. But clearly the brakes are part of the new car which is<br />

hypothetical, so the brakes needs to be hypothetical too. This is why the analysis<br />

either has to b<strong>in</strong>d to an <strong>in</strong>ferred referent <strong>in</strong> the antecedent of the conditional, or be<br />

accommodated with<strong>in</strong> the antecedent of the conditional.<br />

The problem is that there is no clear reason to block global accommodation.<br />

We might be able to say that the result<strong>in</strong>g discourse will not be coherent, but it will<br />

fulfill the requirement of <strong>in</strong>formativity, e.g. There are brakes. If Drew buys a new car,<br />

he’ll ru<strong>in</strong> the brakes with<strong>in</strong> a year with his crazy driv<strong>in</strong>g, is not un<strong>in</strong>formative, just not very<br />

coherent. Global accommodation does not result <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency, nor would it<br />

result <strong>in</strong> what would technically be an ill-formed DRS because of trapp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

However, the relationships between the brakes and car do seem to be similar to the<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of implicit trapp<strong>in</strong>g discussed <strong>in</strong> section 5.1.3, because we want to <strong>in</strong>terpret the<br />

brakes as the brakes of Drew’s new car.<br />

If we choose to “b<strong>in</strong>d,” then we still have to add a new reference marker for<br />

the brakes, a procedure that seems to clearly fit with the description of<br />

accommodation. In this way b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g would here be quite different from normal<br />

b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, where a referent is identified with an already given reference marker.<br />

Geurts (1999) also considers the possibility that the b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g theory could be<br />

modified to put such examples <strong>in</strong>to a third category for resolution, bridg<strong>in</strong>g, where<br />

156

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!