26.01.2013 Views

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

Presuppositions in Spoken Discourse

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Chapter 2<br />

representation <strong>in</strong> some cases. It can therefore be extended to cover other<br />

relationships if they are of a similar type.<br />

Van der Sandt (1992) argued that the procedure for resolv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

presuppositional expressions can be seen as parallel to anaphoric b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g. First, the<br />

presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation as it is understood without a context or without<br />

embedd<strong>in</strong>g is identified. This <strong>in</strong>formation is stored <strong>in</strong> a temporary DRS, called an<br />

alpha-structure. Information <strong>in</strong> the alpha-structure is <strong>in</strong>formation that has to be<br />

processed, and one way for it to be processed is to f<strong>in</strong>d an antecedent. If an<br />

antecedent that is compatible is found, then the presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> the<br />

alpha-structure is bound with this <strong>in</strong>formation. The descriptive <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

associated with the presupposed <strong>in</strong>formation is then moved to the b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g site. The<br />

alpha-structure then becomes empty, and can then be removed from the<br />

representation.<br />

Let’s look at one of the earlier examples with a def<strong>in</strong>ite NP and see how this<br />

would work. (45)b below shows the representation of the first sentence <strong>in</strong> (45)a.<br />

The alpha-structure is written as an italicized DRS prefixed with α, e.g. here α[ z :<br />

bicycle(z), z =?]. In (45)c we can see the alpha-structure with the presupposed<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation triggered by the def<strong>in</strong>ite description <strong>in</strong> the second sentence. The<br />

reference marker z <strong>in</strong> the alpha-structure can be identified with the reference<br />

marker y <strong>in</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong> DRS. Then the descriptive <strong>in</strong>formation associated with the<br />

presupposition can be moved as well. F<strong>in</strong>ally, as seen <strong>in</strong> (45)e, the redundant<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> the representation can be removed.<br />

(45) a. Julia has a bicycle. The bicycle is red. 10<br />

b. [x, y : Julia(x), bicycle(y), x owns y]<br />

c. [x, y : Julia(x), bicycle(y), x owns y, α[ z : bicycle(z), z =?], red(z)]<br />

d. [x, y, z : Julia(x), bicycle(y), x owns y, bicycle(z), z = y, red(z)]<br />

e. [x, y : Julia(x), bicycle(y), x owns y, red(y)]<br />

Note that the representation <strong>in</strong> (45)e is the same as the representation we got for (34)<br />

above, i.e. we cannot tell from the f<strong>in</strong>al representation whether the new descriptive<br />

content that the bicycle was red was able to be associated with the bicycle<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> the first sentence because it was l<strong>in</strong>ked to it via a presuppositional<br />

expression as <strong>in</strong> (45)a or via an anaphoric expression as <strong>in</strong> (34). But this shouldn’t<br />

be a problem because we understand (34) and (45) a to communicate the same<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation, both should be true <strong>in</strong> the same situations, and this is correctly<br />

reflected <strong>in</strong> that they are both given the same representation. There is however a<br />

difference between the two cases <strong>in</strong> how this representation was reached. In some<br />

cases, the <strong>in</strong>put context will differ, but the result<strong>in</strong>g representation, the output<br />

context, <strong>in</strong> both cases will have the same truth-conditions. Note that because<br />

10 Examples like these described <strong>in</strong> the earlier literature on presupposition would be spoken about<br />

<strong>in</strong> different term<strong>in</strong>ology. We would say that the presupposition does not project, and the reason<br />

for this <strong>in</strong> e.g. Karttunen (1973) would be because the presupposition of the second conjunct is<br />

entailed by the first conjunct.<br />

26

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!