23.09.2013 Views

Jaarboek Thomas Instituut 1997 - Thomas Instituut te Utrecht

Jaarboek Thomas Instituut 1997 - Thomas Instituut te Utrecht

Jaarboek Thomas Instituut 1997 - Thomas Instituut te Utrecht

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

AQUINAS AND INTERRELIGIOUS DIALOGUE 33<br />

indeed".<br />

In the final chap<strong>te</strong>r of his prologue, Aquinas draws his<br />

conclusions for how to talk to strangers regarding theological mat<strong>te</strong>rs.<br />

It is remarkable that he is on the one hand very confident of the<br />

convincing power of rational argumentation, but on the other hand<br />

very much aware of the limi<strong>te</strong>d value of reason in theological mat<strong>te</strong>rs.<br />

According to the twofold way of investigating the truth in religious<br />

mat<strong>te</strong>rs, as distinguished in the third chap<strong>te</strong>r, Aquinas says that human<br />

beings are so crea<strong>te</strong>d that they must use two approaches in considering<br />

the truth of God.<br />

The first approach belongs to the realm of reason. This is the<br />

first level of apologetics or in<strong>te</strong>rreligious communication, in which the<br />

adversary should be convinced by demonstrative argumentation. The<br />

second approach belongs to the realm of faith. On this level, human<br />

reasoning cannot have the function of convincing the adversary,<br />

because the power of reason is too weak with respect to God's<br />

revelation. It is even dangerous on this level to try to convince others<br />

by rational argumentation alone, because the other might think that our<br />

faith rests on such weak arguments. In this realm of faith, the use of<br />

rational arguments is not as important as the role of the authority of<br />

Scripture, because the <strong>te</strong>stimony of Scripture confirmed by miracles is<br />

the only way to convince the opponent. Rational argumentation has a<br />

more modest task: it may dismantle the arguments used by the<br />

adversary. Apart from that, reasons of probability" may be employed<br />

as well, though not in order to convince the adversary, but only to<br />

76 ScG I, cap.7: "Ex quo eviden<strong>te</strong>r colligitur, quaecumque argumenta<br />

contra fidei documenta ponantur, haec ex principiis primis naturae inditis per<br />

se notis non rec<strong>te</strong> procedere. Unde nee demonstrationis vim habent, sed vel<br />

sunt rationes probabiles vel sophisticae. Et sic ad ea solvenda locus<br />

relinquitur" (ibid., p. 19).<br />

77 Hoping, o.c., pp. 113-117 equa<strong>te</strong>s rationes probabiles (cap. 7) with<br />

rationes verisimiles (cap. 9), and transla<strong>te</strong>s these words as "dialektische<br />

Argumen<strong>te</strong>", and "Wahrscheinlichkeitsgründe". They are not as strong as<br />

rationes necessariae or rationes demonstrativae, transla<strong>te</strong>d as "demonstrative<br />

Argumen<strong>te</strong>" .

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!