23.10.2013 Views

I527-290 ESRIF Final Report (WEB).indd - European Commission

I527-290 ESRIF Final Report (WEB).indd - European Commission

I527-290 ESRIF Final Report (WEB).indd - European Commission

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

adapting security to the spectrum of risk as it evolves over time 11 .<br />

Similar analyses can, more of less, be made for the other key messages to the effect that they are robust in the sense<br />

of being applicable to both perspectives. At a more detailed level, however, the precise interpretation of the key<br />

messages tends to differ according to view.<br />

At the level of what exact portfolio of security measures to invest in, the difference between the two types of view is<br />

likely to be even more pronounced. Furthermore under the risk-oriented view different context scenario will lead to<br />

different portfolios of measures being optimal, hence giving rise to multi-period investment planning problems.<br />

The observations in Box 1 are indicative of the fact that even the types of analytic approaches to inform security investment<br />

decisions diff er between the views.<br />

The risk-oriented approach in its most extreme form has a well-developed probabilistic risk analysis methodology. This makes<br />

many problems, e.g., various types of aggregation, quantitatively tractable, which under other approaches must be analysed<br />

in a more judgemental fashion. This is true for both investment and operational decision-making.<br />

The consequence-oriented approach, arguably, has time-honoured safety engineering practices like safety factors and margins,<br />

as well as the traditional scenario-based approach to defence planning. More recently the precautionary principle has been<br />

developed in the environmental policy area.<br />

But in addition to being less analytically tractable these approaches run into even more real problems when facing budget<br />

constraints that forbid investments suffi cient for dealing with all conceivable scenarios.<br />

The shortcomings of the consequence-oriented approach are a problem since some types of security investment problems<br />

are hard to properly appreciate within the probabilistic framework of the risk-oriented approach: situations where things like<br />

very long time-spans, very ‘broad’ (some say ‘deep’) uncertainty, rare but dramatic events, or antagonistic behaviour need to<br />

be considered.<br />

As already foreshadowed above our analysis suggests the need to develop approaches intermediate to the extreme<br />

consequence oriented approach and the extreme probabilistic risk assessment – both for professional analysis and public<br />

debate. Therefore we propose a development based on the above-mentioned precautionary principle in the environmental<br />

domain. However the environmental principle deals with another type of issue, viz. whether or not to undertake human<br />

interventions. In security we are instead dealing with countering ‘interventions’ from external actors (including Nature).<br />

Yet – in line with the consequence-oriented view – a straightforward extension of the precautionary principle could be<br />

argued for to the eff ect that if a serious enough case can be made for a risk having the potential to cause severe or<br />

irreversible harm to the public or to the environment, then it should be considered in security policy, e.g. in decisions on<br />

capability development or legislation. One problem with this, as already commented, is the risk for excessive claims on<br />

limited resources 12 .<br />

In response to this WG5 has developed a ‘balanced precautionary principle’. This combines the systematic scenariobased<br />

approach to defining priorities with an all-hazards approach by requiring the scenarios used in priority-setting<br />

to represent the whole space of risks in an unbiased way (cf. the concept of ‘representativity’ in Section 5.4) – it is<br />

not practically feasible to include literally all hazards, but all broad types of hazards should be considered. And a<br />

decision to prioritise some extremely unlikely types of insecurity at the expense of others should be fully transparent<br />

11 Arguably (in particular governmental) security services should be more willing to pay for fl exibility and adaptability than<br />

most other actors, since they form a fi nal defence line and are expected to be able to handle precisely those problems that<br />

no-one else is able to handle. While a normal company can always say that this particular demand is too marginal to cater<br />

to, security services are not really in the position to make that choice.<br />

12 Another problem worth mentioning, which is however a common feature of a precautionary principle and PRA<br />

applied to antagonistic insecurity, has to do infringements on civil liberties. Without special restrictions in this<br />

regard, both the precautionary principle and PRA are likely sometimes to suggest such infringements on bare<br />

suspicion.<br />

131

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!