24.04.2013 Views

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

useful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the conventional nature <strong>of</strong> the praise <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong><br />

antiquity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Epigrams <strong>of</strong> Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros<br />

As mentioned above, two epigrams by Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros, very probably dat<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

the fifth century B.C., are important because they are the only almost contemporary<br />

evidence for the reception <strong>of</strong> Myron’s bronze statue. <strong>The</strong> epigrams praise the sense <strong>of</strong><br />

aliveness associated with the statue, which is identified as a cow <strong>and</strong> a heifer<br />

respectively:<br />

Either a complete hide <strong>of</strong> bronze clothes here a<br />

real cow (boi6), or the bronze has a soul <strong>in</strong>side it<br />

(yuxh_n e1ndon). (Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.717) [92]<br />

Perhaps Myron himself will say this: “I did not<br />

mould this heifer (ta_n da&mal<strong>in</strong>), but its image."<br />

(Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.718) [93]<br />

In the first epigram, Myron is not mentioned, but it is made explicit that the lifelikeness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the bronze cow described is astonish<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> viewer or the reader is told that the<br />

bronze is only a cover that hides the real animal underneath, imply<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, the<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> the statue as if it were alive. Similarly, the reference to bronze as a material<br />

with a soul <strong>in</strong>vites the perception <strong>of</strong> the statue as fully animated, <strong>and</strong> thus as if it were<br />

alive, aga<strong>in</strong>. 118 It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to see that another epigram, an anonymous, advertises the<br />

118 This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> thought accords well with Plato’s assertion, <strong>in</strong> the Cratylus (400a), that the soul is a power,<br />

which when present <strong>in</strong> the body, it causes it to live <strong>and</strong> gives it power to breathe the air <strong>and</strong> be revitalized.<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> animated images <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, see also A. Schnapp, “Are Images Animated: <strong>The</strong><br />

Psychology <strong>of</strong> the Statues <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> C. Renfrew <strong>and</strong> E. B. W. Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient<br />

M<strong>in</strong>d: Elements <strong>of</strong> Cognitive Archaeology (Cambridge, 1994) 40-44. Also, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

a)yuxi/a (“absence <strong>of</strong> soul”) <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate images <strong>in</strong> antiquity, <strong>and</strong> as a topos <strong>of</strong> iconoclastic polemic, see<br />

Donohue, Xoana 40-41, 135, 138n, 155, 161.<br />

72

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!