05.10.2013 Views

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Similarly, if a judgment is insignificant, it is also defective. In order to be meaningful, a<br />

judgment must involve some difference. In order, to be true, it must involve some<br />

identity.<br />

The relation between the significance of a judgment and the moment of difference<br />

is relatively easy to see. In a significant judgment, one that is more than an immediately<br />

evident tautology, there must be some difference between the subject and the predicate. 115<br />

As Hegel often repeats, judgments such as “A tree is a tree,” or “Gold is gold,” lack<br />

significance. 116 Such judgments are clearly true, but they are insignificant. In order for a<br />

judgment to convey significance, there must be at least be some difference between the<br />

subject term and the predicate term. 117<br />

In a true judgment, there must be some form of unity, identity, or connection<br />

between the subject and the predicate. 118 Consider, for instance, the judgment, “the rose<br />

115 It is important to note the very general sense in which Hegel considers judgment, and the very<br />

general meaning that he ascribes the terms “subject” and “predicate.” At the outset of his discussion of<br />

judgment, Hegel claims that the terms “subject” and “predicate,” in their most general sense, are simply<br />

names that designate two distinct features or determinations of the world. He says: “It is therefore<br />

appropriate and necessary to have these names, subject and predicate for the determinations of the<br />

judgment; as names, they are something indeterminate that still awaits its determination and are, therefore,<br />

no more than names” (Science of Logic, p. 624). At the most general level, the structure of judgment<br />

presents the most basic acts of thought – the act of analysis and the act of synthesis. At this general level,<br />

the terms “subject” and “predicate” simply designate the results of analysis, while the copula expresses the<br />

relation or synthesis.<br />

116 See, for instance, the Science of Logic, p. 415. One might even go further and claim that, in<br />

some important sense, such judgments are meaningless. These judgments do convey meaning, but this<br />

meaning is completely parasitic on other judgments. The judgment, “a tree is a tree,” adds no new content<br />

or meaning to our concept “tree.” In this sense, the meaning contained in this judgment derives entirely<br />

from other judgments in which the concept “tree” is employed.<br />

117 This is a necessary though not sufficient condition for the significance of a judgment.<br />

118 This isn’t always the case. In negative judgments, the truth of the judgment stems from the<br />

lack of connection between the two terms. The truth of the judgment, “the rose is not blue,” stems from the<br />

fact that there is no connection between the two terms. Hegel could admit this and simply claim that the<br />

negative judgment is a kind of defective judgment, one that has its telos in the more standard, positive form<br />

of judgment. In and of themselves, negative judgments have very little value. There value comes from (a)<br />

demonstrating the falsity of some positive judgment, and/or (b) from helping us to arrive at a positive<br />

113

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!