05.10.2013 Views

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

along with its attendant conception of immediate experience, often rests upon a sharp<br />

distinction between perceptual awareness and cognition. Our perceptual awareness of the<br />

world presents us with discrete objects. If perceptual awareness precedes cognition, if, in<br />

other words, it presents us with that which is pre-cognitive and thus “immediate,” then<br />

that which is immediately given to us is a discrete plurality and not a manifold. Initially,<br />

this conception seems highly plausible. Perceptual awareness seems to be a passive<br />

recent essay, “Hegel and the Myth of the Given,” John McDowell sums up the point of Sellars essay in<br />

manner that has direct relevance for the present context. He says: “Sellars sets up [or defends] a position<br />

according to which even the most basic perceptual knowledge requires conceptual capacities” (Das<br />

Interesse des Denkens: Hegel aus heutiger Sicht, 76). In other words, Sellars rejects the claim that<br />

immediate or perceptual knowledge precedes judgment or discursive cognition. Following Sellars – who<br />

somewhat playfully describes his arguments in Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind as a “Meditations<br />

Hegeliènnes,” – McDowell ascribes this insight to Hegel. McDowell develops and modifies this Sellarsian<br />

insight in Mind and World, which he describes as a “prolegomena to reading Hegel’s Phenomenology of<br />

Spirit. In Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism and Tales of the Mighty Dead, Robert<br />

Brandom attempts to follow a similar rout back to Hegel through Sellars. If the general line of Hegel<br />

interpretation presented in this dissertation is correct, then this approach to Hegel is highly problematic.<br />

Any approach to Hegel through Sellars must construe Hegel largely in epistemological and semantic terms,<br />

rather than ontological ones. This can already be seen in the brief quote from McDowell’s essay.<br />

McDowell doesn’t claim that “all perception presupposes conceptual capacities or structure,” but rather he<br />

claims that “all perceptual knowledge requires conceptual capacity.” Sellars argues that perceptual<br />

awareness cannot be both (a) immediate while at the same time (b) serving as the basis for knowledge (see<br />

particularly sections I and VII of EPM). Sellars isn’t making a point about perception per se, but rather he<br />

is making a point about perception insofar as it is fit to serve as the basis of justified propositional claims.<br />

In fact, Sellars insists that there is another story to tell about perception, one that treats perception as a<br />

natural – and therefore non-conceptual – process. Sellars merely argues that this scientific account cannot<br />

play a role in our account of how beliefs are justified. Thus for any Sellarsean reading of Hegel, it seems<br />

there will always be two distinct levels of explanation – the causal and the rational/normative. In his essay,<br />

“Naturalness and Mindedness: Hegel’s Compatibilism,” Pippin states the basis of the Sellarsean approach<br />

as follows: “That is, to use again a vaguely Sellarsean formulation: (i) the question at the heart of the basic<br />

spirit-nature dualism at issue is eventually treated as one between the applicability of normative notions and<br />

assessments versus natural or law-like explanations, all within a radically constructivist account of norms;<br />

and (ii) the Hegelian approach does not involve treating the possibility of such a distinction as being based<br />

on any ontological fact of the matter, as, say, between immaterial, causally exempt, and materially, causally<br />

determined beings. The distinction is itself a normative and historical one, not an ontological one”<br />

(European Journal of Philosophy, 7, 1999. Pp. 203-4). In these terms, we can say that nothing captured in<br />

law-like explanations can serve as an epistemic basis for claims about the things as they stand under<br />

“normative notions.” In other words, perception, insofar as it is merely a natural phenomena described<br />

under law-like explanations, cannot serve as a justification for normative epistemic or practical claims. By<br />

contrast to all this, the argument presented in this section attempts to show that perception per se is<br />

conceptually structured. (For an application of the Sellarsian interpretation to practical issues, see<br />

Brandom’s “Freedom and Constraint by Norms.” For a further discussion of the relationship between<br />

McDowell’s Mind and World and Hegel, see Michael Quante’s “Reconciling Mind and World: Some<br />

Initial Considerations for Opening a Dialogue between Hegel and McDowell.”<br />

189

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!