05.10.2013 Views

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

multiple (at least two) genuine objects exist. Section 2.3 then presents the problems that<br />

arise when we try to conceive the structure of the object in terms of the relation between<br />

unity and plurality. Section 3.1 considers various ways that the understanding tries to<br />

resolve this paradox, drawing specifically on Hegel’s discussion of perception in the<br />

Phenomenology of Spirit. Finally, Section 4 sketches Hegel’s solution to the problem. It<br />

shows how he presents the teleological structure of the object as the only possible – or, at<br />

least as far as he can see, the only available – means of explaining the relation between<br />

unity and plurality.<br />

2.1) The Unity and the Plurality of the Object Derived from the Structure of<br />

Judgment<br />

In forming a judgment, we seek to reflect or capture the structure of the object in<br />

the structure of the judgment itself. Ideally, the structures of the judgment should<br />

recapitulate the structures inherent in the object. In Hegelian terms, the activities that<br />

structure the judgment should recapitulate the activities that structure the object. 163<br />

163 One might object that many forms of judgment do not seek to reflect the structure of the object.<br />

In the basic judgment, “the rose is red,” the subject-predicate structure of judgment reflects the traditional<br />

substance-property analysis of the object. However, the relationship between a disjunctive or universal<br />

judgment and the structure of the object is more difficult to see. Nonetheless, Hegel holds that these<br />

judgments ultimately relate to the structure of the object. Thus, for instance, he holds that the universal<br />

judgment expresses something about the structure of each individual object included in the judgment. In<br />

other words, the universal judgment does not simply rest upon, or refer to, a class of objects as a collection<br />

or set. Thus the judgment, “all dogs are mammals,” makes a claim about the structure of each dog taken<br />

individually, not merely about the collection of things we refer to as dogs. With regards to disjunctive<br />

judgments, the case for the relation between the structure of the judgment and the structure of the object is<br />

somewhat more difficult to make. In this regard, it may be worth remembering our earlier remarks about<br />

the nature of negative judgments. We said that negative judgments have a relationship to positive<br />

judgments that can be defined as both parasitic and instrumental. Negative judgments are parasitic on<br />

positive ones, for their meaning and possibility depends upon the meaning of the positive judgment. The<br />

relationship is also instrumental, since negative judgments are only important insofar as they (a) negate a<br />

debated positive judgment, or (b) bring us closer to forming a true positive judgment. At the very least,<br />

Hegel would argue that disjunctive judgments have an instrumental relationship to apodictic notional<br />

judgments, the highest form of judgment he discusses.<br />

155

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!