05.10.2013 Views

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

THE UNITY OF IDENTITY AND DIFFERENCE AS THE ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Following Leibniz and Hegel, Bradley also argues that the basic structures of<br />

representation present an example of the unity of identity and difference. He says:<br />

As a fact and a given we have in feeling diversity and unity in one whole, a whole<br />

implicit and not yet broken up into terms and relations. This immediate union of<br />

the one and many is an ‘ultimate fact’ from which we start; and to hold that<br />

feeling, because immediate, must be simple and without diversity is, in my view,<br />

a doctrine quite untenable [emphasis added]. 73<br />

Here Bradley further describes the basic structure of the copula or the object as one<br />

whole that contains diversity and unity and as the immediate unity of one and many.<br />

Moreover, he argues that feeling presents an example of this structure.<br />

relationship between plurality and unity in terms of the unity of a process. For a further discussion of this<br />

passage, see Section 4 of Chapter Four.<br />

73 Appearance and Reality, p. 508. In a footnote following this discussion, Bradley acknowledges<br />

Hegel’s psychology as the source for his conception of emotion as a unity that includes plurality. The<br />

footnote reads: “Feeling is certainly not ‘un-differentiated’ if that means that it contains no diverse aspects.<br />

I would take the opportunity to state this view as to feeling is so far from being novel that I owe it, certainly<br />

in the main, to Hegel’s psychology” (Appearance and Reality, 509). In the Philosophy of Mind, Hegel<br />

puts the point this way: “Although in practical feeling, will has the form of simple self-identity, none the<br />

less, in this identity there is also difference; for though practical feeling knows its self-determining to be, on<br />

the one hand, objectively valid, to be determined in and for itself, yet, on the other hand, it also knows itself<br />

to be determined immediately or from outside, to be subjected to the alien determinateness of external<br />

influences (Affectionen). The feeling will is, therefore, the comparing of the immediate determinateness<br />

coming to it from outside, with the determinateness posited in it by its own nature [emphasis added]”<br />

(472Z). Though we may experience feeling as an immediate unity without articulation, this unity<br />

nonetheless contains a plurality that can be articulated. Feeling is a kind of non-articulate or implicit<br />

representation. It reveals to us the relationship between our self, as constituted by our telos, and the<br />

external environment as that which is helpful, harmful, or indifferent in relation to the telos or purpose that<br />

constitutes our self. Thus Hegel describes joy as “the feeling of accordance of my whole being with a<br />

single event, thing, or person,” and he defines fear as “the feeling of my Self, and at the same time of an<br />

evil that threatens to destroy my self-feeling” (Philosophy of Mind, 472Z). So feeling contains the<br />

difference between self and other in the immediate or non-articulated unity of their relation. Hegel holds<br />

that feeling (1) possesses the basic structure of representation, and (2) contains plurality within unity.<br />

Leibniz also emphasizes these points in his account of feeling. In a letter to Arnauld, dated 6 October<br />

1687, Leibniz explains what he means when he says that monads “represent” or “express” the whole<br />

universe. He says: “Expression is common to all forms, and is a class of which ordinary perception, animal<br />

feeling and intellectual knowledge are species. In ordinary perception and in feeling it is enough that what<br />

is divisible and material and what is found common to several beings should be expressed or represented in<br />

a single indivisible being, or in the substance which is endowed with a true unity. We cannot at all doubt<br />

the possibility of such a representation of several things in a single one, since our own souls furnish us<br />

examples” (G.W. Leibniz, 212). Like Hegel, Leibniz agrees that knowledge, perception, and feeling all<br />

have the same basic representational structure. He also agrees that this structure presents an example of<br />

plurality contained within unity.<br />

57

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!