15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

78 Collectivism<br />

Coke induced or compelled James to forego the attempt to<br />

withdraw cases from the Courts for his Majesty’s personal<br />

determination. But no achievement of sound argument, or<br />

stroke of enlightened statesmanship, ever established a<br />

rule more essential to the very existence of the constitution<br />

than the principle enforced by the obstinacy and the fallacies<br />

of the great Chief-Justice.<br />

With respect to the second principle, law as common to<br />

all, Coke developed a model of the law as a single national<br />

limit on all who would limit the freedom of others. The<br />

church, local barons, and specialized tribunals and corporations<br />

all claimed powers over individuals—powers that<br />

Coke successfully argued were reserved to the law courts of<br />

record. He issued countless orders of prohibition and praemunire,<br />

barring these extralegal institutions from arresting,<br />

imprisoning, or taking the property of ordinary individuals.<br />

The third principle, law as a limit on officials, implied<br />

for Coke that law set standards of conduct for officials and<br />

ensured those subject to their authority that the procedures<br />

and rules of fairness embodied in the law could be<br />

enforced. Thus, in Semayne’s Case, a person who barred a<br />

sheriff’s man from entering his house without identifying<br />

himself committed no crime because “every man’s home is<br />

his castle.” In Rooke’s Case, a landowner ordered to pay for<br />

a drainage ditch was entitled to a hearing and to apportionment<br />

of the costs among the others who benefited.<br />

Coke held that law was a source of and a limit even the<br />

powers of Parliament and the King. The King, he argued,<br />

could hold property only according to and within the protections<br />

of law and could exercise powers that were limited by<br />

what Coke argued was the ancient constitution of England.<br />

Parliament could not, as he noted in Bonham’s Case, enact a<br />

law against right and reason, by making a single entity both<br />

accuser and judge in its own cause. Judges, too, were governed<br />

by “what a judge ought to do,” including to rule in<br />

cases before them only according to the reason of law.<br />

The fourth principle inherent in Coke’s legal theories is<br />

that law is a source of rights. Coke was pivotal in reframing<br />

the feudal common law into a law governing commerce<br />

and empire. In so doing, he took old ideas about property<br />

and recast them into new formulae that answered new questions.<br />

Chiefly, he protected what we would now call rights,<br />

but which he saw as those interests and privileges in property<br />

and offices that were understood as the result of long<br />

practice and custom, barring the King from taking privileges<br />

from Parliament, as in Bates’ Case, and barring<br />

Parliament from limiting the prerogative of the King, as in<br />

the Case of Non Obstante. Overall, Coke’s common law<br />

protected the customary rights of the subject from interference<br />

from all, whether from interference by a neighbor, a<br />

sheriff, the King, or Parliament.<br />

See also Common Law; Constitutionalism; Dicey, Albert Venn;<br />

Judiciary<br />

SMS<br />

Further Readings<br />

Bowen, Catherine Drinker. The Lion and the Throne: The Life and<br />

Times of Sir Edward Coke (1552–1634). Boston: Little, Brown,<br />

1991.<br />

Boyer, Allen D. Law, Liberty, and Parliament: Selected Essays on the<br />

Writings of Sir Edward Coke. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2004.<br />

———. Sir Edward Coke and the Elizabethan Age. Palo Alto, CA:<br />

Stanford University Press, 2003.<br />

Holdsworth, William S. “The Influence of Coke on the Development<br />

of English Law.” Essays in Legal History. Paul Vinogradoff, ed.<br />

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1914.<br />

Hostettler, John. Sir Edward Coke: A Force for Freedom. Chichester,<br />

UK: Barry Rose Law Publishers, 1998.<br />

Sheppard, Steve, ed. The Selected Writings of Sir Edward Coke.<br />

3 vols. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2003.<br />

Stoner, James R. Common Law and Liberal Theory: Coke, Hobbes<br />

and the Origins of American Constitutionalism. Lawrence:<br />

University Press of Kansas, 1994.<br />

White, Stephen D. White. Sir Edward Coke and “The Grievances of<br />

the Commonwealth,” 1621–1628. Chapel Hill: University of<br />

North Carolina Press, 1979.<br />

COLLECTIVISM<br />

Collectivism, as the political theorist Andrew Vincent has<br />

noted, was first used in the late 19th century to refer to<br />

those writers and intellectuals who sought to use the state<br />

and the apparatus of government to control or regulate the<br />

economy and other aspects of civil society. It also has been<br />

employed to refer to those who favor an organic view of<br />

society, as opposed to individualism. Collectivism is sometimes<br />

used to designate the same philosophical approach to<br />

social and political life as the term socialism, particularly in<br />

the sense of the favoring of the collective ownership of the<br />

means of production.<br />

Collectivism may be contrasted with individualism in<br />

the areas of methodology and the explanation of social phenomena,<br />

and in terms of social philosophy and ethics.<br />

Methodologically, the individualist emphasizes the<br />

actions of individuals and the consequences of these<br />

actions, whether intended or unintended. Individualists are<br />

of course prepared to acknowledge that the actions of individuals<br />

occur within a social context, and also that some of<br />

their actions may produce results that in turn affect us, as,<br />

say, in the case of interest rates or an economic depression.<br />

Yet for the methodological individualist, to understand the<br />

social world, it is necessary to conceptualize all phenomena<br />

in the social world as ultimately reflecting the actions and<br />

preferences of individuals. Nevertheless, there is some disagreement<br />

among methodological individualists as to what<br />

degree acting individuals should be looked at in social and<br />

cultural terms.<br />

Methodological collectivism exists in both strong and<br />

weaker forms. Strong versions of methodological collectivism

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!