15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

430 Retribution for Crime<br />

fundamental requirements that only the guilty may justifiably<br />

be punished and that all legitimate punishment must<br />

fit the crime. To endorse retributive punishment is, then, to<br />

endorse punishment of crime that is based on principles of<br />

justice, rather than on the punishment’s desirable consequences.<br />

For the retributive punishment of crime to be<br />

actually justified, there must be principles of justice that<br />

actually vindicate punishment.<br />

The retributivist critique of the consequentialist justification<br />

of punishment resonates with the common libertarian<br />

insistence that there are principles of justice that must<br />

be respected in the treatment of individuals even if<br />

violations of those principles were socially expedient.<br />

Retributivism seems to be most consistent with the characteristic<br />

libertarian insistence that individuals, their just<br />

claims, and their rights must be respected and that this<br />

respect precludes treating individuals as resources to be utilized<br />

in programs of social optimization. Hence, if libertarian<br />

doctrine is to embrace punishment, it looks like it must<br />

embrace retributive punishment. However, a more detailed<br />

examination might well reveal fatal flaws in each of the<br />

claims about justice that might be invoked in attempting to<br />

build a positive case for retributive punishment. If that<br />

turns out to be correct, then libertarian doctrine that duly<br />

incorporates sound claims of justice may end up rejecting<br />

all punishment and limiting itself to the endorsement of the<br />

practice of restitution. This sort of endorsement of restitution,<br />

combined with a rejection of punishment, is the position<br />

staked out in Randy Barnett’s well-known essay,<br />

“Restitution: The New Paradigm of Criminal Justice.”<br />

A more detailed examination of the prospects for retributive<br />

punishment requires that we distinguish between<br />

the different sorts of claims about justice to which a retributivist<br />

theorist may appeal. The two main sorts of claims<br />

about justice are claims about desert and claims about<br />

rights. Some retributivists hold that what justifies that extra<br />

whack on the head is that the agent who has performed a<br />

disfavored action thereby deserves the whack on the head.<br />

The whack is his just desert, and the morality of a system<br />

of just deserts allows—or even requires—that the whack be<br />

delivered. Other retributivists hold that what justifies that<br />

extra whack on the head is that the agent has violated<br />

another’s rights and that the only way to acknowledge that<br />

a right has been violated and, at least in this sense, annul the<br />

violation is to deliver the whack. A morality based on rights<br />

allows—or even requires—the retributive whack. Quite<br />

often retributivists do not attend carefully to which of these<br />

two sorts of claims about justice claims they are invoking.<br />

Both the desert and the rights defenses of punishment<br />

require that we look backward to determine whether a<br />

given agent may be punished, rather than looking forward<br />

to the possible desirable consequences of punishing him.<br />

We must determine whether the agent actually performed<br />

the wrongful act that would make him deserving of the<br />

whack or whether he actually engaged in the violation of a<br />

right that would, in some sense, be annulled by delivering<br />

the whack. In either case, the guilt of the agent is essential<br />

to the justification of the punishment. Moreover, the magnitude<br />

of the justified whack will track the magnitude of the<br />

wrongful or rights-violating action by the guilty party.<br />

Thus, these forms of retributivism seem to limit justified<br />

punishment to the proportionate punishment of the guilty.<br />

Of course, it is this backward-looking feature of retributivism<br />

that leads its consequentialist critics to charge that<br />

retributivism is merely pointless vengefulness.<br />

How well do these two forms of retributivism—desert<br />

and rights—fit within the general libertarian perspective? It<br />

is clear that the desert form does not accord well with libertarian<br />

doctrine inasmuch as it is predicated on rejecting the<br />

proposition that it is the role of political and legal institutions<br />

to employ their coercive powers to ensure that individuals<br />

get what they deserve. The dutiful son deserves his father’s<br />

estate, whereas the prodigal son does not; yet that does not,<br />

from the libertarian perspective, justify the use of coercive<br />

means to deliver the estate to the dutiful son. The armchair<br />

fan of mass murder who revels in the news of some monstrous<br />

attack in which he plays no part more deserves to suffer<br />

than the petty thief; yet that does not, on the libertarian<br />

perspective, justify coercively imposing the greater suffering<br />

on the fan of mass murder. Indeed, it would violate the rights<br />

of the prodigal son to deprive him of the estate that his foolish<br />

father has bequeathed to him. Similarly, it would violate<br />

the rights of the devotee of mass butchery to inflict on him<br />

the suffering he so richly deserves. Libertarians do not<br />

believe that desert-based theories of morality are subject to<br />

coercive enforcement; indeed, desert is part of the moral<br />

domain, the coercive enforcement of which violates people’s<br />

rights. Hence, no libertarian embrace of retributive punishment<br />

can be founded on justice as desert.<br />

It is justice based on a respect for rights that is the crux of<br />

libertarianism. But does even this notion of justice really support<br />

retribution—as opposed to supporting only restitution?<br />

One common argument against the belief that justice<br />

demands rights-based retributive punishment depends on a<br />

false belief in the rights of the king or—in more modern<br />

contexts—the rights of society or “the people.” The picture<br />

that the opponent of retribution presents is this: Extracting<br />

restitution from an agent who has inflicted a loss on some<br />

individual is based on our correct belief in that individual’s<br />

rights; but any accompanying punishment of the agent will be<br />

based on our incorrect belief that the king or society or “the<br />

people” also have some right that the agent’s actions have violated.<br />

The additional whack of retribution is based on this<br />

belief in additional rights held by the king, society, or “the<br />

people.” According to the antiretribution argument, because<br />

these additional rights do not exist, any defense of retribution<br />

that depends on them must be unsound. Indeed, many friends<br />

of retribution quite willingly embrace the idea that, whereas<br />

restitution vindicates the rights of the individual, punishment<br />

per se vindicates the rights of the state or “the people.”

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!