15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

92 Consequentialism<br />

Stuart Mill, who referred to it as a “doctrine worthy only of<br />

swine.” Mill’s alternative utilitarian proposal introduces the<br />

distinction between “higher” and “lower” pleasures and<br />

assigns to the former, “the pleasures of the intellect, of the<br />

feelings and imagination, and of the moral sentiments, a<br />

much higher value as pleasures than to those of mere sensation.”<br />

Mill’s argument rests on the premise that anyone<br />

“competently acquainted with both” types of pleasures<br />

would prefer the higher to the lower pleasures. From this<br />

argument, he famously concludes that it is “better to be<br />

Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.” Thus, Mill’s<br />

alternative to hedonism aims to answer two perennial questions<br />

in the history of utilitarianism: (1) How should utility<br />

be characterized? and (2) To what extent is it possible to<br />

generalize across the utility functions of individuals?<br />

In moral philosophy, consequentialism contrasts<br />

most sharply with deontological theories of morality.<br />

Deontological theories hold that the rightness of an action<br />

is determined by features of the action, not by the consequences<br />

to which the action gives rise. Immanuel Kant’s<br />

moral theory is particularly representative of this approach.<br />

Kant argued that an action’s consequences are ultimately<br />

irrelevant to its rightness or wrongness. The moral worth of<br />

an action depends “not on the realization of the object of<br />

the action, but solely on the principle of volition in accordance<br />

with which, irrespective of all objects of the faculty<br />

of desire, the action has been performed.” It is the consistency<br />

between the principle of volition and the commands<br />

of reason that determines an action’s rightness. According<br />

to Kant, the rationality of autonomous agents requires that<br />

our actions be “universalizable,” that is, that it be possible<br />

for us rationally to conceive of and will a world in which<br />

our actions are generally done. Against consequentialism,<br />

then, Kant concludes that a particular action can be morally<br />

wrong despite the fact that, if carried out, it would lead to<br />

maximally good consequences.<br />

Consequentialism has been charged with being morally<br />

lax in some circumstances and overly strict in others. It is<br />

commonplace to illustrate these charges by appeal to familiar<br />

types of examples. First, in some circumstances, it is<br />

relatively clear that violating commonsense moral prohibitions<br />

(e.g., prohibitions against lying and breaking<br />

promises) would lead to maximally good consequences.<br />

Generally speaking, consequentialist theories must hold<br />

that such circumstances would make these actions morally<br />

permissible or, more strongly, morally required. This fact<br />

prompts the charge of laxness aimed at consequentialist<br />

moral theories and, specifically, at utilitarianism. It is conceivable<br />

that there are cases in which, say, lying about an<br />

individual’s guilt would lead to better consequences than<br />

would telling the truth. But critics of consequentialism<br />

charge that surely it would be wrong to punish an innocent<br />

person simply because so doing would lead to better consequences.<br />

One standard consequentialist reply has been to<br />

claim that it is the consequences of rules not the consequences<br />

of acts that are relevant to moral assessment. The<br />

distinction between rule and act utilitarianism makes it possible<br />

to offer the moral argument that one should act on<br />

rules of the sort that, if generally followed, maximally good<br />

consequences would result. In line with ordinary morality,<br />

then, the rule utilitarian is in a position to claim that morality<br />

prohibits lying and promise breaking and, moreover,<br />

that it does so for good consequentialist reasons.<br />

The second charge (viz., that consequentialism is overly<br />

strict) derives from the fact that this theory denies the moral<br />

relevance of intentions in assessing the morality of actions.<br />

By so doing, it risks winding up committed to a theory of<br />

blameworthiness and punishment on which individuals are<br />

held accountable for the results of their actions, even when<br />

these results were in no sense intended. In other words,<br />

some consequentialist theories hold individuals responsible<br />

for their actions when ordinary morality tells us that these<br />

individuals were not morally at fault. Such theories also<br />

stand accused of being overly strict on the grounds that they<br />

see all actions as being either morally required or forbidden.<br />

For example, if morality demands that our actions<br />

maximize utility, it will normally be the case that there is<br />

exactly one action that morality allows. All other actions<br />

will be prohibited.<br />

As we might expect, the distinction between consequentialist<br />

and deontological theories has its parallel in political<br />

theory. As applied to this domain, consequentialism is most<br />

often set against theories of individual rights. Rights theorists<br />

claim that some ends, no matter how good, cannot be<br />

legitimately pursued because so doing would violate the<br />

rights of individuals. John Rawls put the point succinctly in<br />

his A Theory of Justice, claiming that utilitarian forms of<br />

consequentialism do not “take seriously the distinction<br />

between persons.” But it is important to recall that not all<br />

consequentialist theories are utilitarian and, more interesting<br />

for our purposes, that consequentialist theories can be consistent<br />

with and, indeed, supportive of highly individualist<br />

understandings of justice. In fact, rights theorist John Locke<br />

makes explicit appeal to consequentialist considerations in<br />

his argument for property rights. Locke writes,<br />

he who appropriates land to himself by his labour, does not<br />

lessen, but increase the common stock of mankind: for the<br />

provisions serving to the support of human life, produced<br />

by one acre of inclosed and cultivated land, are (to speak<br />

much within compass) ten times more than those which are<br />

yielded by an acre of land of an equal richness lying waste<br />

in common.<br />

David Hume similarly appeals to consequentialist<br />

considerations in his argument for a stable system of property<br />

“fix’d by general rules.” Hume tells us that, “however<br />

single acts of justice may be contrary, either to public or

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!