15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Rights, Theories of 437<br />

The most important and controversial feature about<br />

individual rights is that they override all other moral<br />

claims. If individuals have a right to liberty, then they may<br />

not be physically compelled or coerced to take actions<br />

merely because those actions are morally worthwhile.<br />

Individuals may not be compelled or coerced to engage in<br />

actions that, for example, constitute virtuous behavior, fulfill<br />

their moral obligations to others, achieve the political<br />

common good, or promote the greatest good for the greatest<br />

number. Further, individuals may not be coercively prohibited<br />

from doing what is morally wrong but to which they<br />

have a right. People should be free to choose the morally<br />

wrong course of action provided that it does not entail violation<br />

of the rights of others. Physical compulsion and coercion<br />

may be used only in defense against or in response to<br />

the exercise of physical force or coercion, which is generally<br />

understood to include extortion and fraud.<br />

The central problem faced by contemporary libertarian<br />

theorists is how to justify giving the right to liberty such<br />

fundamental importance. Why is the right to liberty more<br />

important than being virtuous, fulfilling our obligations to<br />

others, achieving the common good, or promoting the<br />

greatest good for the greatest number? The answers to that<br />

question take different forms and provide a way to classify<br />

various theories of individual rights. What follows is a short<br />

summary of the various positions.<br />

Moral skepticism holds that there is no moral knowledge<br />

and, therefore, there is no problem faced by the advocate<br />

of the right to liberty. Because we do not know what<br />

actions are morally worthwhile, we do not have to show<br />

why liberty is more important than these other allegedly<br />

worthwhile actions. Of course, the problem with this approach<br />

is that it is too sweeping. If no one knows what is morally<br />

right or wrong, then one also does not know that people<br />

have a moral right to liberty or that it is wrong to initiate<br />

physical force or coercion.<br />

Intuitionism contends that the right to liberty is a selfevident<br />

moral truth and impossible to reject if one has any<br />

moral insight at all. Yet is that so? What do we say to those<br />

people who have moral insight but do not grasp the right to<br />

liberty as a fundamental truth? That right may indeed have<br />

some kind of basic status, but it certainly seems to be something<br />

that needs to be demonstrated, not merely intuited.<br />

Contractarianism argues that individuals either actually<br />

do, or hypothetically would, agree to respect the liberty of<br />

each other in order to live together, and that that agreement,<br />

which may be explicit or tacit, is the ultimate source of their<br />

right to liberty. Nothing is more ethically basic than social<br />

agreement. The central issue here is, however, whether this<br />

approach is based on what people agree to or to what they<br />

should agree to. If it is the former, what happens to the right<br />

to liberty if people do not agree? What follows if they do<br />

not accord fundamental social importance to the right to<br />

liberty? Would there be no basic right to liberty? If it is the<br />

latter, then why should persons agree to respect each<br />

other’s liberty? What is the basis for that claim? Is social<br />

agreement not ethically basic after all?<br />

Utilitarianism holds that people have the right to liberty<br />

only if that right promotes the greatest good for the greatest<br />

number. Liberty is valuable only because of the good consequences<br />

it produces. Because a society based on the right<br />

to liberty tends to produce the greatest good for the greatest<br />

number, people have that right as a rule. Of course, it may<br />

not be true that protecting an individual’s liberty promotes<br />

general social utility, and when following that rule does not<br />

promote overall utility, then there is no justification for following<br />

it. Utilitarian advocates of rights frankly admit that<br />

possibility, but see no alternative. Their critics believe that<br />

it is precisely in those cases where protecting an individual’s<br />

liberty does not promote the general good that an individual’s<br />

right to liberty is most needed. Such critics claim<br />

that the utilitarian approach cannot capture the nonconsequentialist<br />

character of individual rights.<br />

Deontologism, or duty ethics, holds that an individual’s<br />

right to liberty is not based on producing good consequences<br />

in any sense. Rather, that right is based on the<br />

insight that individual human beings are ends in themselves<br />

and not merely means to the ends of others. Thus, it is<br />

morally wrong to use people for purposes to which they<br />

have not consented. However, one can ask, why are people<br />

ends in themselves? What makes them so, and exactly how<br />

does that require that their liberty be respected? Further,<br />

does their status as ends in themselves require only that<br />

their liberty be respected? Could it not also require the fulfillment<br />

of other moral obligations?<br />

Virtue ethics claims that the aim of life is the human flourishing<br />

of the individual, and the development of an individual’s<br />

moral character is central to that activity. Yet the<br />

dispositions that constitute such character cannot be morally<br />

worthwhile unless they are the result of human choice.<br />

Physical compulsion and coercion deny human choice. Thus,<br />

liberty is necessary for the exercise of individual choice and<br />

the achievement of virtue. Nevertheless, important issues<br />

remain. What happens when people do not choose virtuously?<br />

What happens when people choose courses of action<br />

that are personally and socially destructive? Do people have<br />

a right to choose what is morally wrong? How can an individual’s<br />

right to liberty be based on what is necessary to<br />

choose virtue? Is something more than liberty required to<br />

support the choice of virtue? What if someone’s flourishing<br />

depends on violating someone else’s rights?<br />

However, it has been contended that many of these issues<br />

are the result of failing to see that rights are an irreducible<br />

moral concept. Rights do not exist for the sake of achieving<br />

human flourishing (or virtue), nor are they some ultimate<br />

moral duty. They are not like any other moral concept.<br />

Rather, rights exist for solving a uniquely political/legal<br />

problem. This problem stems from the highly individualized,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!