15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Hodgskin, Thomas (1787–1869) 227<br />

Third, although goods are scarce in man’s natural state,<br />

this situation is rectifiable. However, nature is not generous.<br />

Men must work, indeed work in cooperation with<br />

others, to increase the supply of wealth at our disposal.<br />

Unfortunately, a shortcut to wealth is available; we can<br />

simply take what others have produced through their labor,<br />

rather than laboring ourselves. This ability to gain at the<br />

expense of others, not innate aggression, sets the stage for<br />

conflict between men.<br />

Fourth, we are capable of love, at least in a limited way.<br />

Hobbes is widely thought to have espoused egoism, in that<br />

the only things we desire are those that conduce to our private<br />

good. Yet Hobbes is aware that love unites families,<br />

despite our having little general affection for strangers. In a<br />

contest between self and strangers, people are prone to act<br />

selfishly.<br />

Finally, we are not naturally moral. Hobbes argued that,<br />

in the absence of moral or affectional restraint, opportunities<br />

to gain by violence will often prevail. At the same time,<br />

people will move to defend themselves, including engaging<br />

in preemptive warfare. No one trusts anyone, cooperative<br />

activity is impossible, and there is “continual fear, and the<br />

life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.”<br />

The method by which men extricate themselves from<br />

this terrible state is morality. Hobbes provided a list of laws<br />

of nature, laws based exclusively on the use of our reasoning<br />

from our general interests and not on intuition or<br />

religion. The first and most fundamental law of morality<br />

requires us to confine ourselves to peaceful interchange with<br />

others except when attacked; at that point, we may defend<br />

ourselves. This moral law leads to several others, among<br />

them that we may claim only as much, but no more liberty,<br />

for ourselves as we are willing to grant others, and that we<br />

honor our agreements.<br />

These laws of nature, Hobbes maintained, are “eternal<br />

and immutable.” If so, why, then, is there a need for the<br />

State to enforce these laws? Hobbes argued that these laws<br />

of nature are weak and cannot be relied on to enforce themselves.<br />

One should refrain from making war on others, but<br />

only if they do not engage in warfare first. However, if one<br />

can gain from aggressive action of this sort, there is really<br />

nothing to stop us. Contracts, Hobbes noted, are “mere<br />

words” and “of no strength to bind a man.” What man<br />

needs is security, without which we remain in the most<br />

awful of worlds, the state of nature. This security can only<br />

be obtained, Hobbes concluded, through the creation of a<br />

State, to which each of us concedes our power.<br />

It is here that Hobbes blunders and blunders badly. First,<br />

there are many devices that might conduce to the security<br />

necessary to peaceful coexistence, not the least being<br />

parental training of the young. In addition, there are peer<br />

pressure, reputation, and the formation of voluntary defensive<br />

agencies such as security companies. Second, the idea<br />

of government by general consent was, on Hobbes’s own<br />

assumptions, impossible. Consent is signified by words. If<br />

words do not bind, the agreement to create government is<br />

impossible, and we are stuck in the state of nature.<br />

This problem gives rise to the most pervasive dispute<br />

among libertarians—whether it is in our interests to have a<br />

state, albeit limited in its extent, or market anarchism. The<br />

statist thinks the state is necessary to prevent chaos, but its<br />

activities can and should be confined to a narrow range—<br />

the minimal state (minarchism). Market anarchists argue<br />

that the free market is capable of doing everything, including<br />

protecting the free market. Nevertheless, both schools<br />

agree that Hobbes’s political conclusions are wrong. Indeed,<br />

if he were right, all governments, including the worst in history—Stalin,<br />

Hitler, Nero—are legitimate because, however<br />

bad they are, they are better than the state of nature.<br />

Hobbes’s singular contribution to the development of political<br />

theory is the clarity of his discussion of the general<br />

nature of morality, in which he shows what a proper state,<br />

if there can be any such, would do: namely, forbid interpersonal<br />

aggression and nothing else. Hobbes saw that peace,<br />

prosperity, and the possibility of each of us living the best<br />

life as we each understand it lies solely in the prevention of<br />

violence. Thus, he deserves pride of place as the founder of<br />

liberalism.<br />

JN and DT<br />

See also Coercion; Contractarianism/Social Contract; English Civil<br />

Wars; Liberalism, Classical; Locke, John; Natural Law;<br />

Revolution, Right of<br />

Further Readings<br />

Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Richard Tuck, ed. New York:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1991.<br />

Locke, John. “Second Treatise on Government.” Two Treatises on<br />

Government. Peter Laslett, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2005.<br />

Oakeshott, Michael. Hobbes on Civil Association. Indianapolis, IN:<br />

Liberty Fund, 1975.<br />

HODGSKIN, THOMAS (1787–1869)<br />

Thomas Hodgskin was one of the most original libertarian<br />

theorists in Victorian England. His first major work was<br />

Travels in the North of Germany (1820). This two-volume<br />

travelogue, which is interspersed with political commentary<br />

on “the much governed countries of Germany,”<br />

frequently discusses the inefficiency and waste of governmental<br />

projects. Hodgskin even suggests that police functions<br />

should be placed in private hands. In 1825, Hodgskin<br />

published Labour Defended against the Claims of Capital,<br />

a tract cited repeatedly by Karl Marx and later to cause

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!