15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

V<br />

VIRTUE<br />

The term virtue is often used equivocally in both scholarly<br />

and ordinary discourse. The term is sometimes employed<br />

to mean whatever is morally good or appropriate.<br />

However, it has traditionally been used more precisely<br />

to mean certain qualities of character, or dispositions to<br />

choose actions, that are essential to living the right kind of<br />

life. As Aristotle defined it in the Nicomachean Ethics,<br />

virtue “is a settled disposition toward actions by deliberate<br />

choice.” According to Aristotle and those who have<br />

followed him, one acquires virtues by engaging in virtuous<br />

acts: “A man becomes just by doing just actions and<br />

temperate by doing temperate actions; and no one can<br />

have the remotest chance of becoming good without doing<br />

them.” He ridicules those who, “instead of doing virtuous<br />

acts, resort to merely talking about them and think that<br />

they are philosophizing and that by doing that they will<br />

become virtuous.”<br />

If one uses the term to refer to certain dispositions of a<br />

person’s character that both produce and express moral<br />

excellence, which is the traditional meaning of virtue and<br />

the one used here, then there is no easy or direct connection<br />

between libertarianism and virtue, either theoretically or<br />

particularly. With respect to libertarian political theory, the<br />

idea of using the state to directly promote virtuous conduct<br />

would violate its central principles. Practically speaking,<br />

the pluralism embedded in libertarianism would appear to<br />

leave no room for using force to promote the “right kind of<br />

life” or the “right sort of character,” although libertarians<br />

have no problem with individuals or groups achieving or<br />

promoting those things through voluntary means, such as<br />

education, persuasion, and example.<br />

There is a general tension in classical liberalism<br />

between the concern with procedural rights, which specify<br />

limits, constraints, and procedures rather than goals or<br />

ends, and the traditionally nonprocedural and substantively<br />

specified characteristics of virtue found in much of traditional<br />

moral theory. Indeed, a central element of classical<br />

liberal theories of social order is the observation that individuals<br />

can interact for mutual benefit without any real<br />

knowledge or concern about each others’ characters.<br />

Although virtue and liberty are not directly linked, a<br />

number of connections between the two may nonetheless<br />

be identified. Libertarianism implies free and open markets,<br />

and it has been a common view, at least since Adam<br />

Smith, that such markets promote certain widely appreciated<br />

virtues, such as honesty, thrift, civility, probity, temperance,<br />

tolerance, and prudence. Having to please others<br />

in order to be successful in the market, rather than being<br />

able to use force to accumulate wealth, provides a certain<br />

discipline that engenders the habits just mentioned.<br />

Free-market competition among providers of goods and<br />

services tends to reward those who exhibit such traits and<br />

to encourage others to emulate them. But can free-market<br />

competition emerge if such virtues are absent? In recent<br />

years, there has been substantial interest in the issue of<br />

whether markets are dependent on preexisting moral dispositions.<br />

The question has become especially acute since<br />

the fall of the Soviet empire because markets in a number<br />

of formerly communist countries have had difficulty taking<br />

root, although no state appears to have been systematically<br />

and deliberately preventing them from doing so. The<br />

issues and problems are complex, and their study offers<br />

many opportunities for advancing our knowledge of how<br />

self-ordering systems emerge and sustain themselves. It<br />

may be that the rule of law and well-defined property<br />

rights are more central to the development of markets than<br />

is any given set of moral dispositions. At the same time,<br />

the establishment of the rule of law and well-defined property<br />

rights may be dependent in some important way on<br />

moral beliefs and attitudes. It is not obvious which must<br />

precede the other.<br />

521

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!