15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

34 Bioethics<br />

perspective of ethical theory. At the end of the 19th century,<br />

Herbert Spencer, in his book, The Principles of Ethics, tried<br />

to provide a scientific foundation for a libertarian ethics.<br />

However, since then, there has been no such comprehensive<br />

effort. Both Murray Rothbard in The Ethics of Liberty and<br />

H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. in The Foundations of Bioethics<br />

provide fundamental theories of justice, not comprehensive<br />

theories of ethics. Others, such as Tibor Machan in<br />

Generosity and Ayn Rand in The Virtue of Selfishness, focus<br />

on analyzing a particular moral principle and do not provide<br />

a theoretical foundation for an entire libertarian theory of<br />

personal morality, although Rand clearly thinks she does.<br />

What, then, would the theoretical foundations of a libertarian<br />

personal morality look like? First, like libertarian<br />

theories of justice, liberty would have to occupy a place of<br />

paramount importance. Several well-known ethical theorists,<br />

albeit not libertarians, make liberty central to their<br />

theories of personal morality. Aristotle, John Stuart Mill,<br />

and Immanuel Kant are among the most famous moral<br />

philosophers to stress that, without freedom, including the<br />

freedom to make mistakes, there can be no true moral conduct.<br />

Without choice, there is no morally blameworthy or<br />

praiseworthy actions, no good or bad conduct, no good or<br />

bad people. There is only more or less determined action,<br />

with little room for the intentional internalization of a moral<br />

code or personal moral growth. In addition, each of these<br />

great philosophers also stipulated what they believed that<br />

personal code should be.<br />

Aristotle put forward a theory known as “virtue ethics.”<br />

In the Nicomachean Ethics, written as a practical guide for<br />

his son, Aristotle stressed both that human beings naturally<br />

strove to better themselves and that virtue was the path to<br />

moral goodness. Aristotle argued that the good person is<br />

one who intentionally chooses to make practical wisdom<br />

and virtue habitual. The virtues at issue were temperance,<br />

courage, pride, truthfulness, fairness, and friendliness,<br />

among others.<br />

John Stuart Mill, the most famous proponent of utilitarian<br />

ethics, argued that actions should be judged as right or<br />

wrong based on how well they contributed to the aggregate<br />

good of society, usually expressed in terms of the maximization<br />

of happiness. As he contended in On Liberty: “I<br />

regard utility as the ultimate appeal on all ethical questions;<br />

but it must be utility in the largest sense, grounded on the<br />

permanent interest of man as a progressive being. . . .”<br />

Immanuel Kant is known as the father of rationally<br />

based deontological theories of ethics. Most deontological<br />

or duty-based systems of ethics are theological, but Kant’s<br />

Enlightenment version claims its foundation in reason.<br />

Kant held that ethics provided the laws of freedom, the way<br />

physics provided the laws of nature. “Nothing in the<br />

world—indeed nothing even beyond the world—can possibly<br />

be conceived which could be called ‘good’ without<br />

qualification except a good will.”<br />

Kant proffered a rule, a categorical imperative, in which<br />

he argued that appeals should be made to common human<br />

reason: “Can I will that my maxim becomes a universal<br />

law?” This one simple sentence is the rational foundation of<br />

all moral conduct, Kant argued. Morally correct actions are<br />

conduct that one would find reasonable for everyone. The<br />

nonaggression axiom, embraced by libertarians, fits Kant’s<br />

categorical imperative perfectly. It is logical not to aggress<br />

against others because, were everyone to do so, there would<br />

be chaos. With the help of Kant’s categorical imperative<br />

and its corollary maxim of “respect for persons” as a precondition<br />

of liberty, an individual is set to cultivate a good<br />

will and become a better person. Although controversial,<br />

this assertion is all but self-evident given the history and<br />

theoretical foundations of libertarianism.<br />

Many argue that there is something fundamentally<br />

unlibertarian about the concept of the aggregate good,<br />

which is inherent in all utilitarian theories, from the utilitarian<br />

theory of Mill to the social contract theories of<br />

Rousseau and Rawls. Individual freedom is not something<br />

that should be tolerated (or extolled) because of its utility,<br />

nor is it something to be traded for a promise that basic<br />

material needs will be met. Liberty is important in and of<br />

itself, not simply as a means to an end. For many libertarians,<br />

individual freedom is of such paramount importance<br />

that, even if it could be proven that liberty did not further<br />

the general interests of society, they would not be willing<br />

to give it up.<br />

One way out of this utilitarian dilemma is to root the<br />

primacy of liberty in an Aristotelian ethics or a Lockean<br />

notion of natural rights. Aristotelian ethics has rightfully<br />

been criticized as subjective and culture-bound and can<br />

really only be redeemed by grounding it further in either<br />

natural law or reason.<br />

Under natural rights theories, freedom is either a Godgiven<br />

right or an inherent aspect of human nature. The<br />

problem with this type of theory is that some libertarians do<br />

not believe in God or God-given rights, and others have<br />

misgivings about the scope of natural rights. Who is to say<br />

what qualifies as a natural right and on what grounds?<br />

Perhaps the answer lies in what is reasonable. If that is the<br />

case, then we need not rely on natural rights at all—and can<br />

simply make reason the foundation of liberty. We are thus<br />

brought back to the Enlightenment notion that reason can<br />

lead to right action in the same way that it can lead to a just<br />

system of government.<br />

One theory that grounds liberty in reason was put forth<br />

by Kant in his book, Foundations of the Metaphysics of<br />

Morals. Libertarians who embrace this approach argue that<br />

rational beings do not want others interfering in their decision<br />

making, either public or private, economic or moral. In<br />

short, respect for others necessitates the primacy of liberty.<br />

Once it is clear that liberty is a necessary precondition of<br />

any libertarian theory of ethics and that reason is the only

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!