15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

14 Anti-Corn Law League<br />

human history. ...The idea of ‘free contract’ between<br />

the potentate and his starving subject is a sick joke, perhaps<br />

worth some moments in an academic seminar<br />

exploring the consequences of (in my view, absurd) ideas,<br />

but nowhere else.”<br />

For these anarchists, the key issue is the existence of<br />

power, not who wields it. By rejecting any meaningful role<br />

for market forces and private property, however, social<br />

anarchists leave unresolved the mechanism for coordinating<br />

the economic activity necessary to sustain human existence<br />

and generally retreat into evocations of the need for<br />

community.<br />

Some libertarians reject anarcho-<strong>capitalism</strong> and argue<br />

instead for a government limited to dispute resolution and<br />

preservation of order. They object to the variance in standards<br />

of justice and procedure likely to occur when law<br />

depends on market forces—law will vary among places<br />

and persons, just as the varieties of breakfast cereals do.<br />

The problem with this argument, as Friedman has<br />

observed, is that it assumes the government is controlled<br />

by a majority that shares a taste for similar principles of<br />

law. If such a majority exists, market mechanisms also will<br />

produce a uniform set of legal services. If such a majority<br />

does not exist, however, anarcho-<strong>capitalism</strong> better serves<br />

to produce a diversity of legal services that would satisfy<br />

diverse tastes.<br />

A further libertarian criticism of anarcho-<strong>capitalism</strong> is its<br />

failure to limit the types of law that will be produced by<br />

market forces. If almost everyone desires restrictions on<br />

some particular behavior, an anarcho-capitalist society<br />

might impose such restrictions, whereas a libertarian one<br />

will not. Some anarcho-capitalists (e.g., Murray Rothbard<br />

and his followers) have made similar criticisms of the analyses<br />

of other anarcho-capitalists (e.g., David Friedman).<br />

Andrew Rutten uses game theory to explore various problems<br />

with an anarchist society, including this one. Given the<br />

potential for abuse of power even in anarchy, these critics<br />

argue, it is not necessarily clear that anarchy will be better at<br />

protecting rights than the state. A related libertarian criticism<br />

is that an anarchist system will break down as the result of<br />

collusion between the firms providing law and order so that<br />

eventually something like a state emerges, but without constitutional<br />

limits on state power.<br />

See also Anarchism; Friedman, David; Minimal State; Rothbard,<br />

Murray<br />

Further Readings<br />

AM<br />

Benson, Bruce. The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the State.<br />

San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy, 1990.<br />

Cowen, Tyler. “Law as a Public Good: The Economics of Anarchy.”<br />

Economics and Philosophy 8 (1992): 249–267.<br />

Friedman, David D. The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical<br />

Capitalism. 2nd ed. LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1989.<br />

Kellogg, Robert, and Jane Smiley. The Sagas of Icelanders. New<br />

York: Viking Penguin, 2000.<br />

Morriss, Andrew P. “Miners, Vigilantes & Cattlemen: Overcoming<br />

Free Rider Problems in the Private Provision of Law.” Land &<br />

Water Law Review 33 (1998): 581–696.<br />

Rutten, Andrew. “Can Anarchy Save Us from Leviathan?” The<br />

Independent Review 3 (1999): 581–593.<br />

ANTI-CORN LAW LEAGUE<br />

In 1815, following the Napoleonic Wars, Great Britain<br />

imposed import duties on a large array of agricultural goods<br />

from abroad. Known collectively as the “Corn Laws,” these<br />

laws prohibited the importation of foreign agricultural<br />

goods until the domestic price of wheat reached 80 shillings<br />

per quarter. In 1828, the laws were amended to allow a sliding<br />

scale of import duties—the duties fell as the prices at<br />

home rose. Still the measures remained highly protectionist<br />

and were condemned by liberal thinkers and statesmen<br />

around the British Isles. Some 11 years later, in 1839, the<br />

Anti-Corn Law League was founded to lobby for the repeal<br />

of these laws. The leaders of this group were Richard<br />

Cobden and John Bright, both of whom served in<br />

Parliament. They argued for a comprehensive liberal<br />

agenda, but at the forefront of their efforts were the causes<br />

of international trade and peace. Their efforts proved successful.<br />

In 1846, the Corn Laws were effectively repealed<br />

(although modest tariffs on some farm goods remained),<br />

and the league was disbanded.<br />

Libertarians have long praised the efforts of the Anti-<br />

Corn Law League, arguing that it serves as a model for<br />

modern-day interest groups wishing to enact libertarian—<br />

indeed, radical—reform. Historians and economists, however,<br />

continue to debate whether the league was, indeed,<br />

fundamentally libertarian in orientation. Some have<br />

claimed that the league was composed primarily of selfinterested<br />

manufacturers who believed that lowering<br />

domestic tariffs on agricultural goods would open markets<br />

for their industrial products. Foodstuffs would enter Britain<br />

from the continent, and, in exchange, manufactured items<br />

would flow abroad. These manufacturers, it is argued, had<br />

the same goals as libertarian free-traders, but their reasons<br />

were far from ideological. The efficacy of the league also<br />

has been debated at length. The league, to be sure, saw its<br />

goal achieved. But was it crucially instrumental in ending<br />

the Corn Laws? Or, instead, were the tariffs repealed primarily<br />

as a matter of simple economic necessity? On both<br />

points, the evidence is mixed.<br />

There were, no doubt, members of the league who had<br />

little interest in a broader liberal agenda. But, in the main,<br />

the league was indeed a radical group comprising people

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!