15.11.2014 Views

capitalism

capitalism

capitalism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Posner, Richard A. (1939– ) 385<br />

Critics of communitarianism claim, however, that there<br />

are conceptual problems with denying some notion of individualism<br />

because in advancing their views communitarians<br />

are conducting themselves individualistically. They are<br />

assuming that they have the right to voice their views, that<br />

they need no permission from the community to disagree<br />

with the community, which is, at least in large portions of<br />

the West, individualistic.<br />

Another source of support for the idea of positive liberty<br />

is a deterministic view of human behavior, which is increasingly<br />

popular. Those people who do not fare well may not<br />

be regarded as having failed, but more as incapable of<br />

doing what needs to be done for them to get ahead in their<br />

lives. As John Rawls puts the matter, the assertion that we<br />

“deserve the superior character that enables us to make the<br />

effort to cultivate our talents is ...problematic; for such<br />

character depends in good part upon fortunate family and<br />

social circumstances in early life for which we can claim no<br />

credit.” Thus, having more or less (or a higher or lower<br />

quality) of what others have is of no moral significance, but<br />

a matter of the various impersonal forces that shape a person’s<br />

life. Hence, it may be inferred that all who are disadvantaged<br />

are victims of circumstances and do not deserve<br />

their lot. This view counters the conception of negative liberty<br />

that libertarians embrace—namely, that once adult men<br />

or women are free from interference from others, their<br />

flourishing or lack thereof in life must be largely their own<br />

achievement.<br />

In any case, despite the attempt to dismiss the debate<br />

between advocates of negative and positive liberty, the<br />

issue appears to have staying power because political<br />

philosophers will continue to affirm certain kinds of liberties<br />

or rights for human beings. Which are the proper kind<br />

is something that will remain both theoretically and practically<br />

significant.<br />

Libertarians embrace the view that only negative liberty<br />

is consistent with a free society, believing as they do that<br />

individual goals are attainable without involving government<br />

and without mandating what libertarians deem to<br />

amount to involuntary servitude from others. They support<br />

this position from a variety of perspectives, but it is central<br />

to all these that individual human beings are sovereign and<br />

must not be used against their will by others, including the<br />

government.<br />

See also Constant, Benjamin; Freedom; Liberty in the Ancient<br />

World; Rights, Individual; Welfare State<br />

Further Readings<br />

Berlin, Isaiah. Four Essays on Liberty. London: Oxford University<br />

Press, 1969.<br />

Constant, Benjamin. Political Writings. Biancamaria Fontana,<br />

ed. and trans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.<br />

TM<br />

Conway, David. Classical Liberalism: The Unvanquished Ideal.<br />

New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995.<br />

Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty. London: J. W. Parker and Son, 1859.<br />

Narveson, Jan. The Libertarian Idea. Philadelphia: Temple<br />

University Press, 1988.<br />

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. “The Social Contract” and Other Later<br />

Political Writings. Victor Gourevitch, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1997.<br />

POSNER, RICHARD A. (1939– )<br />

Richard A. Posner is a judge and a legal theorist. Posner<br />

is a judge of the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh<br />

Circuit, a senior lecturer at the University of Chicago Law<br />

School, and the leader of the modern law and economics<br />

movement.<br />

Posner held a variety of positions in the Johnson<br />

administration and taught at Stanford University before<br />

joining the Chicago faculty in 1969. At Chicago, he participated<br />

in George Stigler’s famous Industrial Organization<br />

Workshop, and he developed close ties with many members<br />

of the economics department. He soon began using<br />

the tools of neoclassical economics to analyze legal issues,<br />

and in 1973, Posner published his textbook, Economic<br />

Analysis of Law. That book has become a classic and is<br />

now in its sixth edition.<br />

In the opening chapter of Economic Analysis of Law,<br />

Posner writes: “Many lawyers still think that economics is<br />

the study of inflation, unemployment, business cycles, and<br />

other mysterious macroeconomic phenomena remote from<br />

the day-to-day concerns of the legal system. Actually, the<br />

domain of economics is much broader.” Economics, he<br />

argues, “is the science of rational choice in a world—our<br />

world—in which resources are limited in relation to human<br />

wants. The task of economics, so defined, is to explore the<br />

implications of assuming that man is a rational maximizer<br />

of his ends in life, his satisfactions—what we shall call his<br />

‘self-interest.’ ” Such a statement may seem obvious to<br />

most economists. However, as Posner notes, it will be quite<br />

surprising to many students of the law, as will the implications<br />

that follow from applying economics to legal issues.<br />

Many legal theorists have charged that the law and economics<br />

approach ignores issues of “justice.” But if one<br />

equates justice with efficiency—as Posner often seems to<br />

do—then such criticism is without merit. After all, efficiency<br />

eliminates waste, and “in a world of scarce<br />

resources waste should be regarded as immoral,” Posner<br />

writes. From this viewpoint, a whole host of socially<br />

disapproved—and currently unlawful actions—cannot<br />

automatically be deemed unjust. Posner notes:<br />

It is not obviously inefficient to allow suicide pacts; to<br />

allow private discrimination on racial, religious, or sexual<br />

grounds; to permit killing and eating the weakest passenger

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!